Reflections
of a Catholic Teacher
Part I
Professor
Paolo Pasqualucci has dedicated himself to the study
of philosophy of law, politics, and of metaphysics.
Among his most recent publications are Introduzzione
à la metafisica dell'Uno (Rome: Pellicani,
1996,151 pp.) dealing with the metaphysical notion
of the One in relation to the metaphysical notion
of God, and Politica e religions, saggio di teologia
della storia (Rome: Pellicani, 2001, 89pp.) which
explores the relationship between politics and religion
from the standpoint of the traditional Catholic theology
of history. He has always participated in the theological
congresses of SiSiNoNo. His contributions
can be found in the Acts of the same, published in
French by the Society of Saint Pius X and in English
(partially) by Angelus Press. |
The following is the first part of the lecture given by
Paolo Pasqualucci, professor emeritus of the University
of Perugia, Italy, on January 3, 2004 at SiSiNoNo's fourth
theological congress held in Rome. It will be serialized
in the next issues of SiSiNoNo. The text has been revised
and expanded by the author. None of this is easy, but it
is fellows like Dr. Pasqualucci that keep doctrine from
impurities and our minds from going soft.
Setting
Up The Discussion
The Marriage of St. Thomas to Modern Thought
A
decree of the Sacred Congregation for Studies (July 27,
1914) under the auspices of Pope St. Pius X, set forth 24
theses drawn from the metaphysics of St. Thomas as "safe
directive norms" for the philosophical and theological
studies of Catholics. Although these norms were not made
binding, the motive for this decree was later elaborated
by Pope Benedict XV in his epistle Quod de Fovenda
of March 19, 1917:
The
Roman pontiffs have constantly maintained that St. Thomas
should be considered as "guide and master" in
philosophical and theological studies, while always preserving
liberty of discussion about that which could and was accustomed
to be subject to discussion in both disciplines.
Popes
Pius XI and especially Pius XII reconfirmed this principle.
Pope John XXIII, however, in his celebrated inaugural address
at the Second Vatican Council, maintained that the "principal
goal" of the Council was not "discussion of this
or that theme of the fundamental doctrine of the Church,
repeatedly expounded in the teaching of the Fathers and
of ancient and modern theologians." For such a purpose
"a council was not necessary." The "principal
goal" of the Council was supposed to consist above
all in
a
leap ahead towards doctrinal penetration and the formation
of consciences, in more perfect correspondence of fidelity
to authentic doctrine, albeit studied and set forth through
the forms of investigation and the literary formulation
of contemporary thought. One thing is the substance of
the ancient doctrine of the depositum fidei,
and another the formulation of its covering: and this
difference should be taken account of in a spirit of patience,
measuring everything by the forms and proportions of a
magisterium pre-eminently pastoral in character.
By
proposing this basic distinction between "substance"
and "covering," between form and content, Pope
John XXIII, while not formally renouncing St. Thomas as
a guide, coupled him with modern thought, which in its various
components is notoriously as distant as can be imagined
from Thomistic metaphysics. This is the great novelty the
Pontiff proposed for the Council to realize as part of its
"principal goal."
Was
it a matter, as many today still maintain, of a simple exterior
adaptation, to make the ancient doctrine more understandable
to moderns and contemporaries? But if it were a simple question
of "exposition" and thus a pastoral matter, was
not the convoking of an ecumenical council a disproportionate
means to do this? Wouldn't it have been enough for the Holy
Office to give instructions to the bishops and the pontifical
universities? Furthermore, if it were a simple problem of
the exposition of doctrine and thus a pastoral issue, why
did Pope John XXIII affirm that, beyond the exposition of
doctrine, it was also necessary to study doctrine
according to the "methods" (as the official French
translation has it) of modern thought? This distinction
between the "substance" and the "covering"
of doctrine was something new in the history of the Church.
It did in fact lead to doctrine being studied in a deeper
way in the light of contemporary thought and thus made to
conform with its methods, thanks to a magisterium of "pre¬eminently
pastoral" character.
It
is well known that the Latin version of this directive by
Pope John XXIII is more concise and seems more moderate
than the official French and Italian versions....But we
must recall that John XXIII did not rectify the vernacular
translations, but allowed them to circulate freely and used
them himself on at least one official occasion in quoting
himself. On this point he maintained an attitude that seemed
intended to legitimize the vernacular translations as representing
the authentic meaning of the more concise Latin text.
Some
Essential Features of Modern Thought
|
|
|
The
SiSiNoNo theological congresses like the one at which
Dr. Pasqualucci gave this presentation publish regularly
the lectures from these symposiums. |
Let
us briefly outline some essential characteristics of modern
thought. We shall focus on the negation of the distinctions
between substance and
accident, of being
and appearance. Doing
this, modern thinkers obscure the nature of intention as
a conscious state of the subject's being, which is realized
in a free and rational will, distinct from its acts which
it nonetheless shapes. Additionally, modern thinkers attempt
to overcome the principle of causality. We will
conclude with a discussion on the negation of the category
of essence, another fundamental premise of modern thought,
focused mainly on the speculation of Martin Heidegger.
We
hope that this exposition will show the intrinsic
incompatibility of "modern thought"
with Aristotelian-Thomistic metaphysics, and the intrinsic
weakness of the "negations" and "overcomings"
on which modern thought is based. The modern school of thought
deliberately places human thought, will, or instincts at
the center of everything, denying any legitimacy to the
very idea of the supernatural.
Discussing
The Errors Of Modern Thought
An
Overview of the Traditional Concepts
Let
us begin with the concepts of substance and accident
as summarized by St. Thomas Aquinas.
The
first concept, that of "substance," aims to express
that which constitutes the very essence of a thing or entity:
that on account of which something is what it is. Even in
everyday speech we are accustomed to speak of "the
substance (or essence)" of a thing in indicating the
essential aspect of a thing, event, or situation, its inner
or constitutive nature, fundamental structure or essence.
The word substance is often used as a synonym for
essence. The second concept, that of "accident,"
denotes by contrast that which appears to be an external
quality or characteristic of a thing, whether permanent
or transitory.
The substance is under (sub-stare) that which appears
and contributes to the very being of something in its essence
while the accident (accidens, that which happens
and strikes the senses) appears from the outside, in perceptible
or phenomenal reality. In a concrete entity, understood
as a whole, substance and accident are found in an inseparable
connection between what is external and what is internal
and profound. The notion of accident implies transiency
and change not affecting the substance. Man, for example,
generally shows a loss of his outer characteristics with
the passing of time, but can we deduce from this fact some
modification in his very human nature? Certainly not. Nor
can we say that this quality is lost with the eventual decline
of his faculties because of sickness and old age. From a
moral point of view, and a general spiritual perspective,
man remains always himself, whatever exterior alteration
may take place in all his qualities, exterior and interior.
An entity therefore both exists and appears:
it appears as it is, but also as it is not. There is a logically
necessary distinction between being and appearance, parallel
conceptually to that between substance and accident. The
substance is in the accidents, in the sense that it is manifest
in them; however, it is not identical with its
accidents, is not exhausted by them and cannot be identified
with them. Substance persists through the changing vicissitudes
of becoming. It involves their essence.
Applying
These Traditional Concepts to "Transubstantiation"
What
would result if we were to look at a dogma of the Catholic
Faith without the help of the notions of substance and accident,
philosophically of Aristotelian origin, re-elaborated in
Scholastic thought, and in particular that of St. Thomas?
Without this philosophical apparatus it is not possible
to understand the singular wonder of transubstantiation
in the most rational and thus the best possible way, in
conformity with a sane intellect.
The consecrated bread and wine maintain their species or
normal appearance, with all their natural qualities or accidents:
colors, odors, density, weight, taste. But their substance
is changed in a supernatural way. By virtue of the words
of consecration, they have become "the body, the soul,
and the divinity" of Our Lord Jesus Christ.
Normally, the substance of something is manifest in the
accidents or qualities of the thing itself. Nevertheless
there can be a difference, because everything that is in
itself exterior and subject to change does not always manifest
its substance. This happens in a supernatural way in the
Eucharist, where the consecrated Host is sacred
not on account of what it appears to be, but because of
what it has intrinsically become after consecration (transubstantiation)
even while retaining all its accidents intact.
This difference can also be found in the realm of secondary
causes. In the case of man, appearance (being external and
therefore accidental) often does not correspond entirely
or even in part to being, that is to the interior
substance in the heart and the mind of a man. As far as
spirit and the ethical life are concerned (the only life
that counts as such for the purposes of our salvation) unity
and difference constantly show themselves to our intellect,
which must collect them, discerning in an adequate manner
in itself and in others the relation between reality and
appearance, that is to say, the difference between exteriority
and interiority, between the transient and the permanent.
How
Traditional Concepts Are Denied in Modern Thought
The
faculties of discernment and judgment are hard to exercise,
yet are of vital importance. Modern thought fails to supply
any principle worthy of the name, prone as it is to simplify
reality from the perspective of the subject. French philosopher
Jean-Paul Sartre wrote:
Modern
thought made great progress in reducing existence to a
series of phenomena [impressions -Ed.] which
manifest it. In this way it sought to eliminate a certain
number of dualisms....Indeed it has above all disposed
of the dualism that opposed that which is inside an entity
to that which is outside. No longer is there anything
exterior to an entity, if by this is understood a superficial
skin that would conceal the true nature of an object from
our vision. This true nature was supposed to be the secret
reality of things. It could be intuited or supposed but
never reached because it was "interior" to the
object taken into consideration. The phenomena that manifest
the entity are neither exterior nor interior; they are
all of equal value, they all refer to other phenomena
and no one of them holds a privileged position....An electric
current, for example... is nothing but the ensemble of
actions that manifest it. No one of these actions is sufficient
to reveal it. At the same time it does not cause us to
see anything behind itself; it refers to itself
and a whole series [of actions]. The result of this, as
it appears, is that the dualism between being and appearance
no longer has a place in philosophy. That which appears
directs us to a whole series of phenomena and not to a
hidden reality capable of drawing to itself all the being
of the entity.... Thus the being of an entity is
precisely its appearance....For the same reason,
the dualism of actuality and potentiality disappears.
Everything is actual. There is no potential behind an
act, nor is there a capacity, nor a virtue [of producing
the action]....Therefore we can indeed refute the dualism
of appearance and essence. The appearance does not hide
the essence, but reveals it: it is the essence
[my emphasis added].
Sartre
here presents principles that he would apply both to nature
and to man. These principles epitomize the characteristic
tendency of modern thought towards a constant, progressive
reduction to a single entity which is not God but man. If
man-whether as an individual or as a collective subject-were
to take himself as the source of the meaning of
existence, of the whole, he would tend to repress
not only every idea of essence but also every idea of transcendence,
of First Cause, of the supernatural! He would then find
himself enclosed in a reality that appears to be constituted
by a simple series of appearances,
by phenomena that could not be reduced to a deeper reality,
would not depend on a first cause, and would not be marked
by a final cause. It would thus be appearance, that is,
the situation, that would make us what we are.
Ethics could no longer be based on absolute principles-because
such principles express an immutable essence that transcends
phenomena-but would rather be a situational ethics
and thus the mere reflex of a finite reality that constitutes
and justifies itself by the demands of action.
In such a vision man, as a subject endowed with intellect
and will, dissolves in the elusive becoming of appearances
and is overwhelmed by the anxious perception of nothingness
on which existentialist thought of the 20th century
has always insisted. If in fact "appearance is the
essence," and if therefore "everything is in actuality,"
if there is no potentiality behind and therefore
prior to an act and no "capacity" or
virtue is realized in it, this amounts to saying that nothing
underlies it. Behind the appearance there is no essence,
and if there is no essence there is nothing behind it or,
if one prefers, nothingness lies behind it. Thus, we come
from nothing and we go to nothing. The inevitable conclusion
constitutes a metaphysical absurdity even more than a moral
one: if nothingness is both before and after us, how did
something-life itself-arise?
A
Criticism of the Materialistic Foundations of Contemporary
Nihilism
To
respond to this traditional objection, materialists have
from ancient times responded that matter should be understood
as eternal and uncreated. This amounts to an act
of faith in matter. Matter is endowed with divine attributes;
matter is implicitly supposed to contain an intelligence
that gives order to the world.
Lucretius
(c. 98-54 BC) wrote that things cannot be born from nothing
by a divine act (De Rerum Natura I, 150) because
otherwise reality would be dominated by chaos and "we
would see everything born from everything, and nothing would
have its own seed, men would be born from the sea, scaled
fish on land, birds would jump from the sky (ibid. I, 158-63).
Nature shows that every thing is born in a definite and
ordered way, through the operation of a generative power
that acts from its own seed (ibid. I, 168; 173-74)
and develops not arbitrarily but in accordance with a determinate,
specific and finite form. To understand this one must recognize
that "a finite part of matter was given to all things,
a limiting part was given to every existent thing for the
purpose of generation out of which it is clear what can
arise" (ibid. I, 203-4). The poet's lyrical
formulation begs an obvious question: "Who has given
a finite matter and thus a determinate form to each and
every thing?" Was it the gods?-No, the Olympian gods,
infinitely distanced from the world, cannot be understood
in this manner; the gods of Epicurus are neither creators
nor judges, but mere ciphers, so to speak. Was it then matter
that gave itself an order on its own, without the intervention
of a demiurge or artificer?...
Lucretius
does in fact think of matter as an entity that produces
and orders itself on its own
without need of a mind and a power to create it. This conception,
with diverse nuances, is at the foundation of all materialistic
philosophies through succeeding generations. It is the well-known
argument of the shoe that makes itself, without need of
a cobbler. Common sense argues that it is absurd.
Yes,
it is absurd. But there is no error that does not have its
share of truth, its appearance of truth and its subtleties
with their own power of fascination. Thus one should attempt
to refute it with rational and measured arguments. Against
Lucretius and his disciples the following arguments are
to be made:
Understanding
"Nothing"
Lucretius
writes that, if things had appeared out of nothing, chaos
would reign, because everything would come to be spontaneously
without any order. Here he contradicts the traditional principle,
which he himself repeats several times, that nothing can
in any way be created from nothing (nil posse creari
de nilo, op. cit., I, 156-57). In fact, only nothingness
can come from nothing and thus nothing can be produced by
nothing, not even
chaos (i.e., birds falling from the sky, fish born
on earth, etc.). Nothingness produces nothing.
It abides forever in its absolute non-being. Non-being is
always something that has no potential being. Nothing is
born in nothingness, nor does anything develop in nothingness,
whether order or chaos.
Nevertheless,
our criticism cannot stop here. The philosophy of Lucretius
obliges him to suppress a concept that is in itself valid-that
of creation out of nothing, as revealed by revelation-by
representing it in a mistaken way. That's important
to look at.
The
target of Lucretius's polemic is the pagan religion that
he knew. In the introductory verses of his poem he exalts
Epicurus for trampling on religion with his materialistic
philosophy. He cites the (legendary) sacrifice of Iphigenia
in Aulis as an example of the evils caused by religion.
The concluding verse of this episode contains an invective
that has been cited over centuries by all the enemies of
religion, that is, "Religion had the power to induce
the practice of such evils," though the word "'religio"
in this context is better translated "superstition."
Lucretius
lived in the age of Cicero, when Roman society was in grave
crisis because of the ongoing civil wars. This crisis arose
from social, political, and economic causes. Religion in
itself can hardly be cited as a cause of the crisis, understood
in the strict sense. But Lucretius's visionary and poetically
seductive materialism seems to express a more profound crisis
than that derived from the lost political ideals of the
Roman republic. It manifests the spiritual crisis of an
entire civilization which could no longer find a place to
stand. In such a situation the world-view of Epicurus was
seductive. It proclaimed a philosophy of renunciation, of
the hidden life, of egoistic retreat into oneself, compensated
at the same time by exaltation of the self as an atom that,
believing itself projected into the eternity of matter,
imputed to itself a lasting cosmic dimension.
The
idea of creation from nothing cannot be found in
the religious mythology nor in the mystery religions of
paganism, nor in Greek philosophy. The Platonic demiurge
does not create matter from nothing, but forms its elements
from an abiding substrate dominated by chaos:
Because
the god wanted all things to be good and that, insofar
as possible, nothing be bad, he then took every visible
thing that was not at rest but was driven about without
order or rule and reduced it from disorder to order, judging
this a superior condition.
In
fact, creation from nothing is a Biblical concept, testified
by divine revelation. Human thought did not arrive at it
on its own. But we cannot suppose that Lucretius meant to
polemicize against the Book of Genesis. The Septuagint,
the celebrated Greek translation of the Old Testament, was
composed from 250 BC to about 130 BC and was not part of
the intellectual furniture of Greek and Roman intellectuals
in the first century BC, even if some general and indirect
knowledge of its teachings cannot be excluded a priori.
Creation
of Adam by Michaelangelo
Be that as it may, the concept of creation out of nothing
as criticized in Lucretius's De Rerum Natura is
not the same as that revealed in the Bible. I must make
this clarification to oppose the mistaken belief that Lucretian
criticism is applicable to the Biblical doctrine. The creation
of the world as described in Genesis does not suppose the
existence of matter prior to the Creator, and thus does
not imply the capacity of matter to give order to itself
independently of a Creator. Creation took place according
to the mind of God who thought and made all things issue
forth from nothing. This happened in a sudden manner, according
to the well-known fiat known from the Bible. This creation
is not the work of nothing but of God, who makes all things
(including man) originate from a state of nothingness with
respect to themselves,
not with respect to
God. This means that the nothingness
from which things arise is that of their prior
lack of existence, not that of an absolute Nothing-Non-being-which
cannot exist if God exists. But God exists "from eternity"
and will always exist. Lucretius, who did not believe in
a reality outside the senses, clearly understood by "creation
out of nothing" either the creative act of an absolute
Nothing, of nothingness as a whole, which, if its existence
be admitted, itself makes the concept of creation impossible;
or else, and more likely, he understands it as the act of
the Platonic demiurge, which makes the world out of an original
substrate which would constitute "nothingness"
as a primordial disorder. In either case his criticism of
the idea of a creation out of nothing cannot be applied
to the true conception of "creation out of nothing"
as reported in the Sacred Scriptures.
Understanding
"Matter"
If
no one gave matter the capacity to distribute itself according
to a form, to grow in a regulated and finite way, something
that implies a plan, an end, it is then necessary to admit
that matter possesses on its own that capacity
which can be seen in a thought or a mind at work. But this
implies that matter as such thinks, that it is
capable of conceiving itself according to all the forms
which it can possibly take. Matter would thus contain not
only creative power but also thought itself, the mind that
directs it. But mind and thought can only be conceived as
something spiritual. Matter would thus contain a reality
(thought) whose characteristics are not those of matter,
which is characterized first of all by extension.
Mind lacks extension and thus, by virtue of this fact alone,
its operations cannot be reduced to that of matter. They
lack that essential condition of finite and sensible beings,
that spatially determined limit that characterizes
matter. The "mind," intelligence, thought, spiritual
ways of being that have their roots in our soul, this complex
and entirely spiritual reality seems in effect unlimited
in comparison with matter. As Anaxagoras said:
All
other things have a part in every thing, but intelligence
is unlimited, independent, and not mixed with anything,
but stands alone in itself.
If
matter were to think, would it not have to be capable of
explaining itself? Instead, it always appears as endowed
with form and forms itself [i.e., as weather elements
swirl and become a hurricane -Ed.] according to
a direction and an end, without ever being able itself to
give any explanation of its being and action, of why it
is what it is. But this insuperable incapacity of matter
seems nevertheless at the same time connected to its ordering
itself according to the idea of an end. Such a connection,
explains St. Thomas Aquinas, legitimizes or even necessitates
the hypothesis of the existence of a Mind that creates and
directs matter. As he says in his Summa Theologica:
We
see in fact that determinate realities lacking reason,
constituted by natural things, operate with a view to
an end. This appears from the fact that they always or
very often operate in the same manner to achieve the best
end; whence it appears that they reach their goal not
by chance but deliberately. But things that do not possess
knowledge [because they lack reason-Ed.] do not tend towards
an end if they are not directed by someone capable of
knowing and understanding, but therefore, there must be
a rational being by whose operation all natural things
are ordered towards an end: and this entity we call God.
"Nature"
Doesn't Run on Auto-Pilot
The
argument of Lucretius for the eternal conservation of all
nature by nature's own operation is totally unacceptable.
Thus
it happens that nature dissolves all things into their
own elements and does not disperse them into nothingness:
if a body were subject to total dissolution, anything
could suddenly disappear before our eyes and cease to
exist: no force would be necessary to realize the separation
of its parts and dissolve its connections. (op. cit.,
I, 215-20)
The
fact that the world has not disappeared up to now does not
result from the fact that every thing has been absorbed
into the constituent parts of its nature. A natural entity
dissolved by death never returns. If it did, one would be
obliged to admit the absurd concept that the dead body of
one's father is contained in the seed of each one of us
and so on infinitely through the generations. The fact that
the world persists up to now results from the fact that
it is maintained in its being by new births that continually
replace the dead. This self-reproduction involves a compensation
of life and death that appears thought out and willed by
Someone in function of the equilibrium of the whole.
For
Christian philosophy the principle of causality [i.e.,
that every effect has a cause -Ed.]: 1)
has an ontological value, that is to say, is really present
in [the being of] things; and 2)
is so evident that it is easily resolved into the first
principles of our mind [i.e., that a thing is what it
is and not what it is not, that one thing cannot be itself
and another at the same time -Ed.]. In fact,
given an entity that has the character of an effect [i.e.,
by participation, contingency -Ed.], the intellect
sees in it the implicit need for a cause. All our theodicy
rests on the principle of causality (Parente-Piolanti-Garafalo,
Dizionario de Teologia Dogmatica).
["Theodicy,"
by the way, is the philosophical apologetic that confirms
the justice of God and whereby right reason demonstrates
the principles of the Faith, the existence of a personal
God, and the necessity and discernibility of revelation
-Ed.]. Pope St. Pius X in Pascendi Gregis said
about Lucretian concepts:
Their
system, overflowing with so many and such enormous errors,
has emerged from the marriage of false philosophy with
the Faith.
Translated
exclusively for Angelus Press from SiSiNoNo (May 31, 2005,
Vol. 31, No. 10). To be continued.
Courtesy of the Angelus
Press, Kansas City, MO 64109
translated from the Italian
Fr. Du Chalard
Via Madonna degli Angeli, 14
Italia 00049 Velletri (Roma)
October
2005 Volume XXVIII, Number 10 |