Chapter
2
Historical
Sketch: The Crises Of The Church
12. The crises of the Church: Jerusalem
(50 A.D.).
It is a habit of the present day to regard contemporary phenomena
as altogether new and as bearing no comparison with past events
either in kind or in degree. Thus the present crisis and the present
renewal are allegedly without parallel in Church history. We shall
see later on how much truth there is in this assertion, but for
the moment it is worth drawing attention to previous crises in the
Church, recognized by historians.
We believe that the Council of Jerusalem, of about the year 50
A.D. should be mentioned first of all. It was the primordial and
fundamental crisis, or moment of separation, in religious matters
between the Synagogue and Christianity; and since separation is
the opposite of syncretism, the famous decree brought by Judas and
Silas to the church at Antioch, which consisted of Christians who
had come over from paganism, cut off at birth that syncretism of
the Gospel and the Torah which would have deprived the new message
of its originality and its transcendence.
The Council of Jerusalem was critical from another point of view
as well; because it separated once and for all theoretical from
practical decisions; principles from their application; and did
so not by adjusting principles but by adjusting their application
to changing circumstances, which adjustment is made in religious
matters under the inspiration of charity. The famous confrontation
between Peter and Paul at Antioch, which occurred after the two
apostles had agreed at Jerusalem that the Jewish law was outdated,
that is, had been surpassed, turned not on a principle but on its
application or, as Tertullian puts it, on conversationis vitium,
non praedicationis.1
What Paul and later, as the event showed, Peter and the whole Church
disapproved of, was Peter's practice of making concessions to the
ritual instincts of the brethren who had come over from the Synagogue;
which differed from his practice regarding those who had come over
from idolatry. These were differences about practical matters or,
if you will, errors resulting from not seeing, or not seeing clearly,
the connection between a principle and a particular situation. They
were disagreements and mistakes of the sort which have continued
to occur in the Church, from Paschal II when he repudiated the concordat
he had signed with the Emperor Henry V, to Clement XIV when he suppressed
the Society of Jesus thus contradicting the non possumus2
of his predecessors, to Pius VII when he retracted the agreements
he had made with Napoleon, accused himself publicly of having given
scandal to the Church and punished himself by not saying Mass for
a time. The distinction between the changeable disciplinary, juridical
and political sphere, and the unchangeable sphere of the porro unum
est necessarium,3
was first drawn by the Council of Jerusalem and constitutes the
Church's first crisis: the historical sphere was clearly distinguished
from the sphere of dogma.
1.“A
defect in behavior, not in teaching.” De Praescriptione Hereti-corum,
23.
2.
“We cannot.”
3.
“There is only one thing necessary.” Luke, 10:42.
13. The Nicene crisis (325 A.D.).
The crisis of Nicea marks the separation of the dogmatic from the
philosophical, and thus emphasizes the supernatural and mysterious
cast of the Christian religion. Arianism constituted an attempt
to deflower the originality of the primitive kerygma by placing
it within the great current of Gnosticism. Gnosticism undermined
the idea of transcendence and removed the notion of creation, by
asset ting that the whole of reality was included in a graded scale
of beings ascending from Matter to Intellect. To maintain that the
Word was not consubstantial with the Father but like Him, satisfied
the yearnings of the human understanding, but it removed the specific
content of the Faith, which proclaims the existence of a single
subject for the following two propositions: this individual here
is a man, and: this same individual here is God. With the conciliar
definitions of Nicea, and subsequently of Ephesus (431) and Chalcedon
(451), the Church distanced herself from the ancient conception
of a god as the perfection of the human, and of religion as the
cultivation of this-worldly values to the exclusion of anything
lying beyond. Jesus Christ could not be a god in the manner of Caesar
or the divine Augusti, or of the gods of Epicurus who although immortal,
perfect and blessed, were of one substance with the substance of
man. He could not be something falling within the limits of previous
philosophical speculation; instead He had to be that thing different
from everything, but not alien, which no philosophy had ever imagined
or which, if it had, had regarded as madness. In short, God ceases
to be the most inaccessible grade of a perfection common to both
man and god, and becomes instead a nature transcending anything
human. Christ is not called the God-Man after the fashion of the
pagans, that is, by a maximal approximation to the divine perfection,
nor by a moral intimacy with God (Nestorius), nor in the manner
of the Stoic paradox according to which the wise man is equal, indeed
superior, to God inasmuch as God is blessed by nature but a wise
man by his own exertions. Christ is ontologically man and ontologically
God, and hence His ontological theandric constitution is a mystery.
This mystery does not contradict reason, because of the very concept
which the new religion brought with it of the nature of the divine
essence; namely that it is a Monotriad, a Three-in-One, in the midst
of which the Infinite thinks and loves itself precisely as infinite;
and therefore that it stands beyond the limits in which the created
intellect operates. If one denies that reason can submit itself
to Reason, one denies it access to the supernatural. What is more,
by denying this submission, one denies reason a proper knowledge
of itself, because one would be denying that it knows itself as
limited and that it therefore recognizes something beyond its own
limit.
The Nicene crisis was thus a decisive moment in the history of
religion, and since every crisis separates an entity from what is
alien to it, and simultaneously preserves the essential character
of that entity, one can say quite simply that the Christian religion
was saved at Nicea.
14. The deviations of the Middle Ages.
The many grave disturbances which the Church experienced in the
Middle Ages were not true crises since through them all the Church
was never in danger of changing its nature or dissolving itself
into something else. Low moral standards among the clergy and lust
for riches and power disfigure the face of the Church, but do not
attack its essence by attempting to alter its foundations.
It is appropriate here to formulate the law of the historical conservation
of the Church, a law which also constitutes her ultimate apologetic
criterion. The Church is founded on the Word Incarnate, that is,
on a divinely revealed truth. She is also given sufficient energies
to conform her own life to that truth: it is a dogma of faith that
virtue is always possible. Nonetheless, the Church is only in danger
of perishing if she loses the truth, not if she fails to live up
to it. The pilgrim Church is, as it were, simultaneously condemned
to imperfection in her activity, and to repentance: in the modern
phrase, the Church is in a continual state of conversion. She is
not destroyed when human weakness conflicts with her own teaching
(that contradiction is inherent in the Church's pilgrim condition);
but she is destroyed when corruption reaches the level of corroding
dogma, and of preaching in theory the corruptions which exist in
practice.
So it was that the Church combatted the movements that disturbed
her in the Middle Ages, but condemned them only when, for example,
the practice of poverty became a theology of poverty which would
have completely disqualified the Church from owning any earthly
goods. For the same reason, the decay in clerical morals, which
the eleventh century reforms so vigorously combatted, was not a
true crisis. Nor was the conflict with the Empire, despite the fact
that the Church was trying to free herself from the feudal servitude
implicit in clerical marriage and in political domination over the
bishops. The Catharist and Albigensian movement of the thirteenth
century, and the further ramification of the Fraticelli, were not
true crises either. These movements, which were begotten of huge
overflows of feeling, and compounded with economic and political
movements, were rarely translated into speculative formulae.4
When they were so translated, as for example in the regressive doctrine
foretelling a return to apostolic simplicity, or in the myth of
the equality of all the faithful at the level of the priesthood,
or in the theology of the Third Age of the Holy Spirit following
on the age of the Son, which had itself followed on the age of the
Father, such doctrinal deviations found the hierarchical Church
ready and able to exercise its office of teaching and correcting,
in which it was often helped by the temporal power which held the
structure of society together. The truths of faith were contested
but not corrupted, and the teaching office of the Church did not
cease to function.
4.
This is not the case with the Catharists.
[Translator's note.]
15. The
crisis of the Lutheran secession. The breadth of the Christian ideal.
The great
eastern schism left the whole structure of the Catholic faith untouched.
The Byzantines did not even directly deny the primacy of the Bishop
of Rome, and an act of reunion could be signed at Florence
in 1439. The heretical movements, which aimed at purging the Church
of its worldly accretions, were powerless to put the Church in danger
by causing it to change from one kind of thing to another. The real
crisis came with Luther, who changed doctrine from top to bottom
by repudiating the principle on which it rested.
The historical
reasons for the great movement of religious revolution in Germany can hardly be understood unless one considers
them in the context of the Renaissance. The latter is often understood
as the restoration of the pagan principle of the absolute naturalness
and this worldliness of man, and thus as something incompatible
with Christianity which is seen as a despising of this world. It
seems to us that this one-eyed view does not accord with the nature
of Christianity. Christianity, based as it is on a God-Man Who is
the restorer and completer of all things, broadens rather than narrows
the mentality of the believer, and enables him to grasp and to elevate
everything that is in conformity with the creative plan, which itself
has as its goal the glorification of man joined to God in the theandric
Christ.
With powerful
mystical sentiment, mediaeval civilization certainly expressed an
essential aspect of religion, namely the relativization of all earthly
reality and its projection towards a heavenly goal. Some would say,
however, that the force with which that aspect was lived out went
beyond due limits, and led to the setting aside or mortification
of values which do not need mortifying, but coordination among themselves
and subordination to heaven. I would say the same. The mediaevals
seem unable to conceive of an ideal Christian except in the form
of a Franciscan friar.5
When, by contrast, we remember the breadth of the Christian idea,
it becomes clear that the Renaissance was a revival of that breadth,
leading the Christian religion to realize the kinship uniting it
to past civilizations within which, buried in sleep, there lay the
values of natural religion, ideal beauty, the civic life and such
treasures as the Phaedo, the Metaphysics, the Venus
of Cnidos, the Parthenon, Homer and Virgil.
Religion has
an expressive capacity much greater than can appear in any one period:
it comes out in successive developments which are not always complete
in themselves but which, taken as a whole, tend towards a progressive
perfection. This growth is hinted at in the Gospel parables of the
seed, and in St. Paul's
references to the Church as an organism that grows up to the full
measure of perfection.
Nor should
it be thought that this assimilation of classical culture began
with the Renaissance and the flight of Greek refugees from Islam,
since it was in fact begun long before, in the midst of the Dark
Ages, by the monastic preservation of Greek and Latin authors. They
were preserved not because the monks found incentives or nourishment
for their devotion in Virgil and Horace, but because, quite distinct
from the all-pervasive ascetical inspiration of that period, the
monks appreciated another ideal which although not ascetic, was
nonetheless religious if Christianity does, as I have maintained,
acknowledge the value of earthly things while directing them towards
heaven. Furthermore, the blending of ancient civilization with the
Christian idea had already happened before the Renaissance in the
primordial form of intellectual development, namely poetry; especially
in Dante's Divine Comedy, in which the myths, thought and
aspirations of the classical world are powerfully combined with
the Christian outlook in a daring synthesis. The limbo of the pagans,
for example, in which the light of natural wisdom, while not bringing
salvation, nonetheless preserves man from the fullness of damnation,
is an outstanding intuition of the mediaeval genius, which was well
aware of the spiritual spaciousness of the Christian ideal that
both includes, and extends beyond, the ascetic world of the cloister.
5.
Luigi Tosti, Prolegomeni alia storia universale della Chiesa,
Rome 1888, p.322.
16. Further
breadth of the Christian ideal. Its limits.
This breadth
of the Christian idea, due to its possessing latent aspects destined
to be made manifest through historical developments, is a teality
running through the whole of Christian thought and is linked theologically
to the unity which exists between the cycle of the creation and
the cycle of the Incarnation, the same divine Word being present
in both. Even without considering the theological causes of this
breadth, an examination of historical events is enough to make its
existence apparent, inasmuch as contrasting schools and styles have
coexisted in the same place. Bellarmine and Suarez lay the foundations
of democracy and popular sovereignty while Bossuet justifies royal
autocracy; Franciscan asceticism preaches the casting aside of all
earthly goods whether material or intellectual while Jesuit realism
builds cities, organizes states and mobilizes all the goods of this
world ad majorem Dei gloriam. The Cluniacs decorate even
the pavements of their churches with colors, gold and gems while
the Cistercians reduce sacred buildings to their bare architecture.
Molina makes much of the freedom and autonomous power of the human
will, asserting it capable of checking divine predestination, and
lowering the divine knowledge to the level of dependence on human
events, while Thomists exalt the absolute efficacy of the divine
decree. The Jesuits proclaim a broad way to salvation while the
Dominicans proclaim the fewness of the elect. The casuists enlarge
the role of the individual conscience when confronted with a law
while the rigorists give the law preponderance over human calculation
about the circumstances of an act. Franciscanism itself, with its
founder's blessing of both Friar Elias and Friar Bernard, contains
two spirits which, by their separations and reconciliations under
the influence of a higher inspiration, explain the internal struggles
in the order.6
If one forgets
this essential spaciousness of Catholicism, the distance between
one form of orthodoxy and another will seem as great as that between
orthodoxy and heterodoxy. This is exactly how it did seem to the
authors of opposed and mutually accusatory schools of thought, but
it was not how it seemed to the magisterium of the Church, which
always intervened to forbid mutual accusation and to safeguard religious
unity at a higher level. Because this breadth was not grasped by
Sainte- Beuve, it seemed to him too amazing que le même nom de
chrétien s'applique également aux uns et aux autres (he had
in mind the laxists and the rigorists). Il n'y a pas d'élasticité
qui aille jusque là.7
Chesterton very perceptively made this breadth the main criterion
in his apologetic for Catholicism. Jacob's prophetic saying should
be remembered: Vere Dominus est in loco isto et ego nesciebam.8
It is nonetheless
necessary to indicate the limits of this large view of the Catholic
religion, which we too regard as a decisive historical criterion.
The large view must not lead to an all embracing Pyrrhonism9
which consumes and syncretizes contradictories, rather than things
which merely differ. It is legitimate to talk in terms of a broad
view when several ideas are seen as a coherent whole, in which there
is a genuine plurality of ideas: that is, when one idea is
not destroyed by the contrasts it has with another. It is, however,
impossible for a human, or any other mind, to make contradictory
terms, that is, true and false, hold together. A coexistence of
that sort would be possible only on an impossible condition; namely
if thought were not oriented toward the being of things, or if being
and non-being were equivalent. Catholicism grants logic precedence
over every other form of mental activity, and logic embraces a plurality
of values within its own truth, but it cannot embrace a plurality
consisting of values and anti-values. A spuriously broad view of
religion leads to theoretical and moral indifference, that is, to
an inability to create an order in living.
6.
A.
Gemelli, // Francescanesimo, 3rd ed., Milan 1936, p.40.
7.
“That the same name of Christian should be applied equally to the
one group and the other....No kind of elasticity could stretch that
far.” Cited in F. Ruffini, La vita religiosa di A. Manzoni, Bari
1931, Vol.1, p.416.
8.
“Truly God is in this place and I knew it not.” Genesis, 28:16.
9.
Pyrrhon of Elis (c.365-275
B.C.), founder of the Sceptics, who held that knowledge of the nature
of things is unattainable. [Translator's note.]
17. The
denial of the Catholic principle in Lutheran doctrine.
It is therefore
a question of seeing how Luther's doctrine could not be included
in the broad ambit of the Catholic system, and how his attack called
into question the principle of the whole system, rather than this
or that corollary.
Inasmuch as
it is a rejection of Catholic first principles, Lutheranism is theologically
irrefutable. When confronted with Lutheranism, Catholic apologetic
finds itself in the position neatly outlined by St.
Thomas:10
it can solve the opponent's objections, but not to the opponent's
satisfaction, since he rejects the principle on which the argument
refuting him is based. For Luther was not merely rejecting this
or that article within the body of Catholic doctrine, (though of
course he did do that as well) but rather rejecting the principle
underlying them all, which is the divine authority of the Church.
Bible and tradition are only authorities for the believer because
the Church possesses them; and possesses them not simply materially
or philologically, but possesses the meaning of them, which she
historically unveils little by little.
Luther, on
the other hand, places both the Bible and its meaning in the hands
of the individual believer, rejects any mediating role for the Church,
entrusts everything to the individual's private lights and replaces
the authority of an institution by an immediacy of feeling which
prevails over all else. The conscience is detached from the teaching
office of the Church, and an individual's impressions, especially
if they are vivid and irresistible, are made superior to any other
rule and are held to establish a right both to believe, and to proclaim
what is believed. What the ancient Pyrrhonism does to philosophical
knowledge, Protestant Pyrrhonism does to religious knowledge. The
Church, which is the historic and moral continuation of Christ the
God-Man, is deprived of its native authority, while the liveliness
of an individual's impressions is called “faith” and declared to
be an immediate gift of grace. The supremacy of this individual
conscience removes the foundation of all the articles of faith,
because they stand or fall according to whether the individual conscience
assents to, or dissents from them. Thus divine authority, which
is the sustaining principle of Catholicism, is extirpated and with
it go the dogmas of the faith: it is no longer the divine authority
of the Church which guarantees them, but subjective individual impressions.
Thus, if heresy consists in holding a truth to have been revealed,
not on the authority of its having been revealed, but because it
accords with a subjective perception, one can say that in Lutheranism
the whole concept of faith is converted into the concept of heresy,
because the divine word is accepted only inasmuch as it receives
the form of an individual conviction. It is not the thing which
demands assent, but assent which gives value to the thing. If then,
by an internal logic, this criticism of divine authority as a theological
principle becomes a criticism of the authority of reason as a philosophical
principle, that is no more than might have been expected a priori,
and it is also confirmed a posteriori by the historical
development of German thought, right up to the fully developed forms
of immanentist rationalism.
10.
Summa
Theologica, l,q.l,a.8.
18. Luther's
heresy, continued. The bull Exsurge Domine.
The germ of
the formidable religious revolution occasioned by Luther is all
contained in the 41 articles condemned by Leo X in the bull Exsurge
Domine of 15 June 1520, though the Pope was certainly unaware
of just how far the rebellion of human thought was to go. As we
have already said, the principle of private judgment is really implicit
in every heresy, and each time the Church lifts her voice against
a particular theological opinion contrary to the faith, that principle
is implicitly rebutted even when it is not explicitly mentioned.
In this instance, however, the principle is expressly stated in
at least one of the condemned articles.
In this series
of condemned propositions, it is difficult to tell which ones the
bull intends to reprove as actually heretical, because, in accordance
with Roman curial usage, after having listed the 41 propositions,
the bull condemns them one and all collectively tamquam respective
haereticos, aut scandalosos, aut falsos, aut piarum aurium offensivos
vel simplicium mentium seductivos.11
This lack of distinction makes it difficult to discern how the
censures are to be distributed, and opens the field to debate among
theologians: an heretical assertion that injures Catholic doctrine
is an altogether different thing from a saying that might mislead
the simple, as the latter constitutes a sin against prudence and
charity, but not against faith.
The propositions
contain, in a developed form, Luther's doctrine of penance, in which
he teaches that the whole efficacy of sacramental penance rests
on the feeling the penitent has of being absolved. Some articles
invalidate the idea of the freedom of the will, which is said to
be moved entirely by grace and to remain de solo titulo.12
Others deal with the supremacy of a Council over the Pope, the uselessness
of indulgences, the impossibility of good works, and the death penalty
for heretics, which Luther held to be contrary to the will of the
Holy Spirit.
There is,
however, one article, No.29, in which the heresy of private judgment
in the choice of beliefs is openly professed by Luther. This article,
stating the true principle of the whole movement, remains as the
only really memorable one: Via nobis facta est enervandi auctoritatem
Conciliorum et libere contra-dicendi eorum gestis et confidenter
confitendi quidquid verum videtur.13
Here the fundamental root, the ultimate criterion, is made plain:
it is private judgment that gives authority to whatever seems
to be true. Of the two sides of a mental act, the one which
apprehends objective being and the other, which is the subjective
act of apprehension, it is no longer the objective being apprehended,
but the act of apprehension itself which predominates. To express
myself in scholastic terms, it is id quo intelligitur14
that predominates over id quod intelligitur.15If
in article 27 Luther proceeds to remove the fixing of articles of
faith and moral law from the hands of the Church, he does no more
than translate article 29 from the individual to the social aspect
of religion.
In conclusion,
the soul of the Lutheran secession was not a question of indulgences,
the Mass, the sacraments, the Papacy, priestly celibacy, or the
predestination and justification of the sinner: it was an intolerance
that the human race carries about fixed fast in its heart and which
Luther had the daring to manifest openly: the intolerance of authority.
Because the Church is the collective historical body of the God-Man,
it draws its organic unity from a divine principle. In such a context,
what could man be, but a part, living by unity with that principle
and by obedience to it? The man who breaks that link loses the forming
principle of the Christian religion.
11.
“As respectively heretical, or scandalous, or false, or offensive
to pious ears, or seductive of simple minds.”
12. “In name only.”
13. “The way is open for us
to deprive Councils of their authority and to contradict their acts
freely and to profess confidently
whatever seems to be true.”
14. “That by which it is understood.”
15. “That which is understood.”
19. The
principle of independence and abuses in die Church.
Once the crisis
is seen in these terms, the consideration of the moral faults of
the clergy and the institutional corruption that followed from it
becomes a secondary question, even though it remains important as
the historical cause that touched off the assertion of the principle
of private judgment. There were certainly enormous abuses of the
sacred on the part of the Church's ministers: one could cite the
monstrous example of Alexander VI threatening his concubine with
excommunication unless she returned ad vomitum.16
Nonetheless, quite apart from the fact that an abuse does not justify
rejecting the thing abused, there is also the fact that the reform
of the Church could only happen, and in the event did happen, in
an orthodox way, thanks to men who were always convinced that Catholics
could not be acting rightly unless they had the seal of approval
of those same churchmen whose vices they continued to castigate,
even while recognizing their authority: and in this they were like
their predecessors St. Francis of Assisi, St. Dominic, St. Catherine
of Siena and the founders of religious orders in the fourteenth
and fifteenth centuries. The reason why the corruption of shepherds
caused only a dispersal of sheep, rather than a true crisis, was
that malpractice was not erected into a dogmatic theory as it was
by Luther. A theory is unlimited, since it contains in its universality
a potential infinity of acts, whereas acts themselves are always
limited. Thus if the theoretical dogma is preserved, the health-giving
principle remains undamaged, and through it the whole of practical
action is saved.
16.
“To her old sins.” Cf. II Peter, 2:22. The threatening letter is published by G. Picotti
in Rivista di storia della Chiesa in Italia, 1951, p.258.
20. Why
casuistry did not create a crisis in the Church.
We cannot
pass on without saying a word about the phenomenon of casuistry,
although it did not create a true crisis in the Church. Gioberti
and some modern authors maintain that it was a real crisis and indeed
the cause of the decline of Catholicism.17
First
and foremost it was not a crisis because fundamentally casuistry
is entirely reasonable and necessary. As the discipline which tells
man how to apply to individual actions ethical tules which of their
nature are universal, theological casuistry has a function analogous
to legal casuistty, or jurisprudence, and is begotten of the necessary
and ever present imperatives of moral action. Its further development
was encoutaged by the Council of Trent which, by declaring that
the priest exercises his office in the sacrament of penance per
modum iudicii,18
emphasized the need for a body of teaching, dealing with individual
cases, which would translate the Church's precepts and the moral
law into practical application. Thus far, there is nothing reprehensible
about casuistry.
What was reprehensible
was its tendency to remove the difficulties of moral obligation
and to make the observance of the gospel law easy, by accommodating
it to human weakness. Equally reprehensible was the wholly philosophic
and rational principle of probability, which placed free will and
individual judgment above the imperatives of the law. So, according
to Caramuel, whom St. Alphonsus Liguori called “the prince of the
laxists,” one ought to make room for a variety of opinions about
what is good and evil, all of them admissible and helpful provided
they have some degree of probability about them, because in his
words divina bonitas diversa ingenia hominibus contulit, quibus
diversa inter se homines indicia rerum ferrent, et se recte gerere
arbitrarentur.19Here
there is some trace of the Lutheran principle of private judgment,
as opposed to the Catholic one of authority.
On the other
hand, casuistic theories which gave pride of place to subjective
impressions in determining one's moral choices were moderated by
the penitent's submission of his conscience to the authority of
a confessor, and thus in some sense to the authority of the Church.
Casuistry was more a science among the clergy, because of their
role as moral advisors, than a moral decline in the popular conscience.
The great bulk of books of casuistry published at that period were
Praxis Confessariorum, and only rarely Praxis Poenitentium.20
It
was, however, easy to drift from benign criteria for evaluating
past actions, which is what casuistry was to begin with, to relaxed
criteria about actions to be performed in the future.
Casuistry
did not amount to a crisis, because the principle that one is free
to choose what law one is bound by was never expressly formulated.
Thus the many propositions condemned by Alexander VII in 1665 and
1666 contain solutions to cases rather than any error of principle.
Therefore it does not follow, as Pascal thought it did, that the
Church's censure of casuistry proves the latter was capable of inducing
a fully blown crisis in Catholicism.
17.
L.R. Bruckberger, Lettre a Jean Paul II, Paris 1979, p. 101.
18.
“By way of judging.”
19.
“The divine goodness has given different characters to men, by which
men may form different judgments of affairs among themselves, and
believe themselves to be acting rightly.”
20.Guides
for Confessors, not Guides for Penitents.
21. The
revolution in France.
The revolution
in France, whatever one may say
about the violent and evil deeds that disfigure it, is rightly identified
with the principles of'89. They would not be principles if they
were merely a promulgation of rights. In fact, they are genuinely
principles, that is, assumptions about the truth, which it is not
permitted to judge and which judge everything else. They are positions
antithetical to the Catholic principle of authority. In that respect
the French events of '89 are historically unimaginable without the
nailing up of the 95 theses on All Saint's Eve 1517, not because
the theses taken individually were subversive, but because the spiritus
agitans molem21
was. That spirit was bound to bring to birth all that was in
fact born of it; bound not by the wickedness of men, nor by the
obstinacy of corrupt churchmen, nor by the ineptitude of hierarchies,
but by the most terrible of all driving and regulating energies
in the human pandaemonium: logical necessity.
Many people
maintain that a rich and abundant mixture of ideas collided with
Catholicism during the revolution and that the causes of the latter
were not all philosophical and religious. I would agree, just as
I would about the Protestant reform. If I conceive of the revolution's
disorderly combat of ideas as being not a proelium mixtum22
but a combat of spirits, a battle of essences, it is because
I see in it a vast and fundamental shift which, in Lucretius's
stupendous image funditus bu-manam...vitam turbat ab imo.23
All Catholic
authors of the nineteenth century, not least among them those usually
classed as liberals, took up the task of criticizing the principles
of the revolution. Manzoni does it in his essay Sulla Rivoluzione
Francese, which modern historiography attempts to discredit
and cast into oblivion. Father Francesco Soave does it in his acute
little work Vera idea della Rivoluzione di Francia (Milan 1793), which is today also condemned to Erebus.
Rosmini does it in his Filosofia del diritto, paragraphs 2080-92, in terms of
a clash between individual and social rights. I am well aware that
a benign interpretation has been forced upon the principles of the
French Revolution by Catholic thinkers and worldly clerics, Catholic
politicians and publicists. They maintain that the principles were
the unfolding of Christian ideas that needed to be unfolded, but
which were not at once recognized for what they were at the time
of their unfolding. There are statements to this effect by senior
churchmen and even by contemporary Popes. We will deal with these
later on, less fleetingly than in this present swift historical
sketch.24
It is however undeniable, and for more than a century it was seen
to be undeniable, that the revolution in France set in motion a
new spirit, a genuinely new principle, which can neither be subordinated
to the Catholic principle nor combined with it on an equal basis.
21.
“Spirit moving the whole.”
22.
“Mixed battle.”
23.
“Disturbs human life most profoundly from its depths.” De Rerum
Natura III, 38.
24.
See paragraph 225.
22. The
principle of independence. The Auctorem Fidei.
Anyone who
glances through Denzinger's famous Enchiridion might be surprised
to find that among the doctrinal documents of the period in which
the great convulsion of the French Revolution occurred, there are
none which directly concern the theoretical presuppositions underlying
the reforming legislation passed by the succession of assemblies
which preceded the Consulate and the Empire. Bonaparte, the mediator
between two ages, finally abolished the most arrogant and anti-Catholic
features of the seven successive constitutions of the 1790s, but
left intact the fundamental informing principle of the modern age,
which underlay all the innovations. That principle, as I have remarked
several times, is the setting up of human values on a purely human,
independent and self-subsistent basis, and the consequent overthrow
of authority.
Liberty, equality and fraternity were not values that had gone unrecognized
by ancient Greek wisdom, or that had not been given universal import
by the Christian religion. Where else could they have come from?
The Stoics had made them dependent on a natural Logos enlightening
every man who came into the world; even if such enlightenment was
ineffective, as the history of slavery, for example, proves. Christianity,
on the other hand, had made them dependent on the supernatural Logos
Who became man, enlightening and effectively moving man's heart.
Since a natural Logos is ideal, not real, it cannot truly
be the principle on which all depends, nor consequently can it be
revered and obeyed unconditionally. The true principle is a supremely
real being that includes the Idea and which, in Christianity, has
made itself a created reality by means of the Incarnation.
The God-Man,
Who is ontologically an individual, becomes a social individual
in the Church. The latter, according to St.
Paul's famous teaching, is the mystical body of the former; hence
dependence on Christ is reflected in dependence on the Church. This
is the principle of authority which rules the whole theological
organism. It was impugned by the Lutheran revolution because, as
has been said, that revolution substituted private judgment in religious
matters for the rule of authority. The correlative of authority
is obedience, and one could equally well say that the first principle
of Catholicism is either authority or obedience; as appears in the
famous Pauline passages about the God-Man being obedient, and obedient
even unto death, that is, with the whole of His life. He was obedient
not primarily to save man (though it is legitimate to put it that
way) but rather in order that the creature should bow before the
Creator and give Him that entire and absolute homage which is the
very goal of creation. That is why the Church of Christ always draws
people to cooperate together, through obedience and abnegation,
and to merge themselves in that collective individual which is the
mystical Body of Christ, taking the individual and his acts out
of their isolation and abolishing any sort of dependence which is
not subordinate to dependence on God.
The political
independence of man taught by the revolution was contained in the
religious independence taught by Luthet and later by the Jansenists.
In this regard Pius VI's constitution Auctorem Fidei (1794)
condemning religious independence, has an importance equal to Pius
X's encyclical Pascendi (1907). When they reproduced the
two documents entire in their famous Enchiridion Symbolorum,
the Jesuit Denzinger and his coeditors displayed a far-sighted
grasp of doctrine. In the Auctorem Fidei too, there are only
a few articles of fundamental importance, and a good many more which
apply these fundamentals as a kind of added ornament. The fundamental
articles are the ones condemned as heretical; the others receive
lesser censures. Setting aside the universal Church, the Pistoians
made the particular church the mediator between the individual and
the divine Word, thus allotting it the place Luther had given to
subjective impressions; and although this pluralized and dispersed
the principle of authority somewhat less than did Luther's much
vaunted principle of private judgment, it effected a shift in authority
from the universal to the particular just the same.
As generally
happens in calls for reform, the Pistoians alleged that there had
been a general obscuring of important religious truths in the Church
in recent centuries (Proposition 1). This allegation was contrary
to the nature of the Church, for in her, truth is indefectible and
can never be obscured in her official teaching. This proposition,
which could fundamentally be considered as an historical judgment,
is followed by others also condemned as heretical, which state that
authority to teach doctrines of the faith and to govern the ecclesial
community resides in the community itself and is communicated by
the community to its pastors. This time it is not the private judgment
of an individual person, but of an individual church which is set
up as the ultimate authority: a universal authority is replaced
by an authority which, although still social, is nonetheless individual.
There is still an obedience to the divine Word, but only insofar
as that Word is conveyed through the medium of what might be called
the private judgment of the diocesan church. That the pope is head
of the Church as its minister, deriving his authority from it rather
than from Christ, is also condemned as heresy; it is a corollary
of the principle that authority resides in the community.
23. The
crisis of the Church during the French Revolution.
Prior to the
revolution of the masses, royal absolutism had already effected
its own revolution and had freed itself from its moral obedience
to the Church, renewed the despotism of the lex regia whereby
quidquid principi placet vigorem habet legis,25
and had
reinforced itself by imbibing the spirit of Lutheran freedom of
conscience. On the one hand the new Caesarism had asserted the ruler's
independence of those laws of the Church which had hitherto strengthened
and tempered royal power for the protection of the people. On the
other hand, it had absorbed the privileges, franchises, immunities,
and immemorial customs which had guaranteed the liberties of the
subject. Few writers attempt to establish to what extent the huge
revolutionary disturbance was simply a reaction of the social mechanism,
and to what extent philosophical aspirations or conspiracies played
a part in it. In any case, events proceeded on an enormous scale
and eradicated principles and convictions like a ventus exurens
et siccans;26
defection
and apostasy took a third of the clergy, compensated for by instances
of unvanquished resistance even to the point of martyrdom; priests
and bishops contracted marriages (subsequently convalidated by the
Concordat of 1801, except in the case of bishops); churches and
religious houses were profaned and destroyed (of three hundred churches
in Paris, only thirty-seven remained as churches); religious symbols
were rejected, scattered or banned (so that Cardinal Consalvi
and his suite wore lay dress when they came to Paris to negotiate
the Concordat); dissoluteness in manners grew and there were licentious
and wayward reforms in public worship and instruction, and sacrilegious
compoundings of the patriotic with the religious. The Civil Constitution
of the Clergy adopted in July 1790 and condemned by Pius VI in the
March of the following year, contained a real error in principle,
in that it secularized the Church and abolished it as a society
prior to, and independent of, the state. If it had remained in force,
it would have wiped every Catholic influence and institution off
the face of French soil; but it succumbed to the rejection of almost
all the bishops and the vast majority of priests, and to the policies
of compromise adopted by Bonaparte.
Hence the
condemnation of the Civil Constitution of the Cletgy is a doctrinal
document concerning the very substance of the Catholic teligion.
It is surprising that Denzinger omitted it.
The total
separation of Church and state was deemed an error by the framers
of the Syllabus, but at least it allows the two societies,
theocratic and democratic, to continue to exist, each with its own
nature and aim. How much more fatal then is the error of absorbing
the Church into the state, and of identifying the latter with human
society in all its aspects. The French Revolution, reduced to its
logical essence, represented a genuine crisis of Catholic principle,
because even though it did not succeed in ttanslating the principle
of independence into social practice, it did implant that principle,
which removes the religious, moral and social orders from their
center, and tends towards the complete dislocation of the social
organism.
Nonetheless,
it is legitimate to doubt that this violent shock to Catholicism
really did constitute a crisis, if one remembers there is no true
crisis when the mystical body is attacked, so to speak, in its sensitive
soul but not in its intellectual or mental one, and when the nucleus,
being endowed with the charism of indefectibiliry, remains undamaged,
even though confusion may be spreading through all the physiological
operations of the body.
25.
“Whatever pleases the prince has the force of law.”
26. “A scorching and drying
wind.”
24. The
Syllabus of Pius IX.
The famous
list of modern errors annexed to the encyclical Quanta Cura of
8 December 1864 is today repudiated by certain theologians,
who are trying to combine Catholicism with those very errors. Alternatively,
it is passed over in silence, or beset by authors who, to avoid
offending that wotld which the Syllabus did offend, boldly
interpret it as the gateway to a further development of error, maintaining
that the progress of thought in our century has shown that at heart
the errors in question were truths. Or lastly, its doctrinal significance,
that is its permanent significance, is flatly denied and it is presented
as merely a passing episode in the Church's mistaken policy of opposition
to the spirit of the age. Even in the Osservatore Romano of
31 May 1980, a French historian associates this outstanding
doctrinal document with “a flare-up of ultramontane, monarchical
clericalism.” Denzinger and his successors displayed both their
sensus fidei and their sensus logicae when they included
it entire in their Enchiridion.
Disputes and
differences arose at once concerning the import of the Syllabus
in relation to Catholic doctrine. Monseigneur Dupanloup, the
Bishop of Orleans, restricted the scope of its condemnations. On
the other hand the Civilta Cattolica, which then enjoyed
great authority, put forward a strict interpretation, recognizing
that the Syllabus condemned the principle upon which the
whole of the modern world rests. Anti-religious writers, who on
the essential point were no less clear sighted than the Jesuits,
opposed the Syllabus because they saw it contained a condemnation
of modern civilization. Some of the condemned propositions gave
rise to disputes in the area of practical moral conduct. Such were
No.75 on the incompatibility of the papacy's temporal and spiritual
powers, and No.76 maintaining that the abolition of the Papal
States would be good for the welfare of the Church. According to
the Civilta Cattolica, anyone who disagreed with the Syllabus
on those points could not be given sacramental absolution. The
clergy of Paris, presided over by their archbishop, decided
on the contrary that such a person could be absolved. In an instruction
given to the members of his Institute before the Syllabus came
out, Antonio Rosmini too had maintained the same position.27
A feature
clearly proclaimed on the very title page of the papal document
is, however, more important than the opinions of moral theologians
on the extent of the obligations the Syllabus imposed on
the faithful. It intends to enumerate praecipuos nostrae aetatis
errores.28
In the last of the articles however, which constitutes a synthesis
of the whole papal condemnation, these errors are identified with
the very substance of modern civilization, which is thus
totally condemned in its principles, but not in the totality of
its parts.
Because it
contains very few condemnations of particular theological points,
and a very sweeping condemnation of the dominant errors of the age,
it would seem that the Syllabus should be taken more as a
denunciation of the state of the world than of the condition of
the Church, and that the gist of its teaching lies in its condemnation
of the spirit of the age.
Of the eighty
articles in the document, few stand out for anyone looking for matters
of universal importance, but these few are indeed decisive.
An independent
reason, which makes no reference to God, recognizes no law but its
own (autonomy), rests on no force but its own immanent strength,
and deems itself capable of carrying man and the world to the fulfillment
of their destiny, is condemned by the censure of the third proposition.
The fifth condemned proposition makes reason an absolute norm, and
describes the supernatural as a product and stage of natural thought:
it therefore denies the dependence of the created word on the uncreated
Word standing infinitely above it; the perfection of divine revelation
thus consists in human consciousness of the divine, and in the reduction
of dogmas to rational theorems. Proposition No.58 is of equal importance,
because it proclaims the individual's ethical decisions to be independent
of any absolute norm transcending his own mind, hence the proposition
constitutes the reflection in practical reason of these same errors.
The juridical application of No.58 is condemned in No.59; namely
that human law is duly constituted by human action alone, prescinding
from any relation to a moral law; the event is the foundation of
justice, and its principle is not the divine Idea, but contingent
reality.
Thus, taken
as a whole, the Syllabus can be seen more as a denunciation
of the modern world than as a symptom of a crisis in the Church,
because the propositions which it draws together relate to a contradiction
between the world and Catholicism rather than to an internal contradiction
between the Church and its own principles, and, as we saw at the
outset, it is precisely the latter which constitutes the definition
of a crisis. It was grasped both by the world and by the Church
that this was the meaning of the Syllabus.
The condemnation
of modern thought proceeds from the Syllabus to Vatican I. The preparatory schema de doctrina
catholica observes it to be characteristic of the age that rather
than attacking particular points which leave the first principle
of religion untouched, homines generatim a veritatibus et bonis
supernaturalibus aversi fere in humana solum ratione et in naturali
ordine rerum conquiescere atque in his totam suam perfectionem et
felicitatem consequi seposse existimant.
Hence, the
difference between the state of affairs envisaged by the Syllabus,
and that of the Church in the present confusion, lies precisely
in the fact that the demands and claims of the world, which were
then external to the Church and opposed by her, have now been internalized
within her, and the antagonism between the Church and world abandoned,
whether by keeping quiet about it, and thus renewing the mediaeval
adage tace et florebunt omnia,30
or by softening it to render it tolerable, or, most commonly,
by weakening the force of Catholicism through making it so broad
as to embrace not the totality of truth, but a syncretistic totality
of truth and falsehood.
The condemnation
of the spirit of the age is certainly undeniable, and can be neither
avoided nor softened, since that spirit is essentially marked by
the errors here condemned. The enormous silence within the bosom
of the Church which is intended to extinguish the papal pronouncement
of 1864, and thanks to which it was acceptable that Vatican II should
not mention it even once, can never annihilate the Syllabus of
Errors, even though it has succeeded in making its very name
a thing to be derided or abhorred.
27.
See on this point the cited edition of the Morale Cattolica,
Vol.III, pp.340-3.
28.
“The principal errors of our age.”
29.
“Men in general have turned away from supernatural truths and goods
and believe they can be content with human reason and the natural
order of things alone, and can attain in them their full perfection
and happiness.”
30.
“Keep quiet and all will be well.”
25. The
spirit of the age. Alexander Manzoni.
In the second
part of his Morale Cattolica,31
in a chapter called in fact “The Spirit of the Age,” which is
the most troubled not only in that work, but in the whole of his
writings, Alexander Manzoni32
is confronted with the same problems as ourselves: that is, whether
the spirit of the age is compatible with the Catholic religion or
not. He finds his solution by a process of analysis and discernment.
Rejecting a false systematization which would accept all or condemn
all, Manzoni examines article by article the various parts of that
heterogeneous compound of ideas; true, useful, sound, false, irreligious
and harmful. Having extracted the good elements, he shows that they
were contained in religion and are derived from it and that the
fault, if there had been one, had lain in not drawing them out,
but leaving it to the enemies of religion to do so. Thus, the analysis
of the spirit of one age should not be made by the light of the
spirit of another, whether past or present, but by the light of
religious truth, which illuminates changing intellects as generations
take their course, while itself standing, changeless, above all
periods by a kind of ucronia.33
By comparing the dominant opinions in a society at a given time,
it is possible to effect that philosophic rather than charismatic
discretio spirituum34
which does not accept or reject a composite whole en bloc,
but discerns merits and demerits by a transhistorical criterion.
But here a
doubt arises. Is the spirit of an age a compound that can be broken
up into its component parts, or is it something (I am not going
to define it) which holds a compound together and gives its parts
an existence other than they have merely as parts? Is not the spirit
that quid which informs the parts, and thus brings them out
of multiplicity and division into a definite and unmistakable unity,
as an individual undivided in itself and divided from everything
else?
The point
Manzoni makes in those pages remains certain at any rate; that the
spirit of an age should not be judged historically, but by a timeless
criterion, that is, by religion and not by history. Of course, this
criterion will not be accepted by someone holding an axiology which
tejects true, noumenal values; but it is the Catholic criterion,
and we intend to use it here in order to discern where the crisis
lies. That kind of criterion is therefore not only a legitimate
one, but the only one legitimate.
Judgments
which Catholicism and systems opposed to it make about the worth
of the same object, for example the value and dignity of the human
person, may seem identical; but the identity is only apparent, since
Catholicism finds the reason for this dignity where the other systems
do not. In both cases man is loved, but in the one he is deemed
lovable in himself, while in the other he is not; it is rather a
higher principle, Lovable in Itself, which makes him lovable in
turn.
By this example
one can grasp what it is that constitutes the spirit of an age,
a society or a system. It is the ultimate ground, irreducible
to anything further back, which renders each moment of the system
or the age intelligible; the caput mortuum,35that
is, that final idea in which the whole is resolved and which is
not itself resolvable into anything else. Thus the spirit of an
age is not a complex of ideas, but what unifies such a complex,
and cannot itself be broken up. The spirit of the age is the analogue
in social life of what the Bible calls the tree or heart
in the life of an individual person;36
the place whence spring a man's thoughts, good or evil, saving or
damning, and whence the good or bad fruit proceeds, according to
whether the tree or heart be good or bad itself. From the religious
point of view, man is radically good or radically bad, and his destiny
turns on the moment of death.37
31.
See
op.cit. Vol.11, pp.413-59 and Vol.111, pp.323-9.
32.
Alexander Manzoni (1785-1873), Catholic apologist and the most famous
of Italian novelists. [Translator's note.]
33.
“Timelessness.” I expounded the Manzonian solution at length in
an address to the Arcadian
Academy on 24 April 1979, now published in its Atti
pp.21-44.
34.
“Discernment of spirits.”
35.
“Fixed point.”
36.
Matthew, 7:17 and 15:18.
37.
See paragraph 202.
26. The
modernist crisis. The second Syllabus.
The crisis
stated in the Syllabus was a crisis of the world more than
of the Church. The crisis stated in the second syllabus, constituted
by the decree Lamentabili of 3 July 1907 and the encyclical Pascendi
of 8 September of the same year, was, on the contrary, a crisis
of the Church itself. The difference between Pius X's document and
Pius IX's is obvious from their titles: Pius IX was listing praecipuos
nostrae aetatis errores,38
Pius X denounces errores modernistarum de Ecclesia, revelatione,
Christo et sacramentis.39
Every philosophy contains a potential theology. The purely theological
matters contemplated in the teaching of Pius X, are the mature fruit
of that philosophy of independence condemned in the first Syllabus.
As the titles differ, so does the nature of the 65 condemned
propositions. They no longer concern a spiritual state of affairs
pertaining to the world but external to the Church; they concern
rather the corrosion of the Catholic mind itself; they no longer
concern the separate parts of a system, but the spirit immanent
in them all.
That is also
made plain by the fact, noted in the encyclical, that the modernist
plures agit personas ac velut in se commiscet,40
being at once an historian, a critic, an apologist and a reformer.
I do not believe that Pius X was making a moral condemnation of
trickery or hypocrisy (plurality of masks) when he noted the existence
of this variety of characters, even though traces of a certain Achitophellian41
deception are perhaps to be seen in some of the propagators of the
doctrines in question; as they are, are they not, in some of their
opponents? I believe rather that the multiplicity of characters
or masks shows that the document is not condemning separate limbs,
but a single spirit, which is ultimately the spirit of independence.
To proceed
in the same manner as we did in the case of the first Syllabus,
we will examine some of the document's principal articles
in order to show its condemnation of this spirit. Proposition No.59
condemns the error that man subjects unchanging revealed truth to
his changing judgment, thus subordinating truth to history. This
sort of reduction of the truth to an advancing human sentiment,
which proposes and reproposes the datum of religion as a
kind of unknowable noumenon, is also rejected in article
No.20, as it removes the “religious sense” from its dependence on
the authority of the Church.42
It is expressly admitted that the Church is reduced to the task
of merely registering and sanctioning opinions dominant in the Ecclesia
discern,43
which is in reality no longer being taught at all. By denying
that revealed truth can oblige one to give an internal or personal
assent, as distinct from a merely external assent as a member of
the Church, proposition No.7 asserts the existence in each individual
of an intimate core of independence from truth; so that truth is
binding by virtue of being subjectively apprehended, rather than
by virtue of its being true.
Proposition
No.58 is no less weighty: Veritas non est immutabilis plus quam
ipse homo, quippe quae cum ipso, in ipso et per ipsum evolvitur.44Two
sorts of independence are proclaimed here. First, man as an historic
being is made independent of man as a nature, the latter being entirely
absorbed in the historicity of the former. The proposition amounts
to a denial of the existence of the eternal idea containing the
exemplars of real natures, a denial of that indisputable element
of platonism without which the idea of God collapses. The second
independence proclaimed is, more generally, that of reason from
Reason. Human reason, which we know is the greatest container in
the world,45
is nonetheless itself contained in another container, which is the
divine mind. This second container is denied in proposition No.58.
The assumption made in the condemned article to the effect that
truth develops with, in and through man, is therefore false. It
does develop in that way, but not wholly. It is not true that truth
comes to be as man comes to be: it is created intellects that undergo
change, even the intellects of believers, even those of the social
body which is the Church; they all tend towards the same truth,
by their own activity which varies from individual to individual,
from generation to generation and from civilization to civilization.
This alleged independence of the mind from immutable truth tends
to confer a kind of mobilism on the entire content of religion,
as also on its container, the mind.46
Proposition
No.65 seems to me to be of great interest and to provide much food
for thought when compared with the last proposition of the Syllabus.
Pius IX declared Catholicism incompatible with modern civilization.
Pius X condemns whoever says it is incompatible with modern
science.
So the Church
then is incompatible with modern civilization, but modern civilization
is not to be identified with science. Religion is compatible with
human thought, not in the sense that it passively submits to all
the forms, some of them mistaken, through which the history of thought
may wander, but in the sense that it is always compatible with that
truth at which thought's wanderings are directed. The document expresses
this difference by proclaiming religion compatible with true science.
In any event, we have two condemned propositions: Catholicism
is compatible with modern civilization (Pius IX) and Catholicism
is incompatible with true science (Pius X). From a comparison
of the two condemnations, it becomes clear that modern civilization
and true science do not correspond. While the Church distinguishes
between modem civilization and true science, she does not cease
condemning the spirit of the age. There can be knowledge which is
true in a civilization which is false, but it is then garbed in
a false spirit of which it must be stripped, by a kind of reclaiming
action, so that it can be reclothed in the truth which is found
in the Catholic system and so be regulated by its true principle.
38.
“The
leading errors of our age.”
39.
“The errors of the modernists concerning the Church, revelation,
Christ and the sacraments.”
40.
“Mixes in itself, as it were, several characters, and plays their
parts.”
41.
See II Samuel, 15-17.
42.
The heart of modernism is really this: that the religious soul draws
the object and motive of its own faith from within itself, and not
from outside. This is the diagnosis given by Cardinal Mercier in
his Lenten Pastoral of 1908.
43.
“The learning Church.” A standard phrase distinguishing the main
body of believers Ecclesia discens from the bishops, or sometimes
the clergy at large, who are the teaching Church Ecclesia docens.
[Translator's note].
44.
“Truth is no more unchangeable than man himself, since it evolves
with him, in him and through him.”
45.
Rosmini, Teosofia, III, 1090, nat. ed., Vol. XIV, Milan
1941. See indices, for the word Idea.
46.
See paragraphs 157-62.
27. The
pre-conciliar crisis and the third Syllabus.
In this brief
historical overview our intention is to outline cursorily some previous
crises in the Church. We are almost entirely ignoring their political
aspects, saying nothing about theit social repercussions, and are
hardly touching on disciplinary changes, since the Church's discipline
depends on its doctrine.
Examining
crises in the Church, we have found that they only occur when a
contradiction of the constitutive and governing principles of the
Church arises within the Chutch itself, rather than in the world
outside. This kind of contradiction of principle is the “constant,”
as mathematicians put it, of all crises. The crisis which had arisen
in the world outside the Church and been demonstrated in the first
Syllabus, and which, at the beginning of this century, had
again been identified by Pius X when it began to spread into the
Church's internal life, was recognized yet once more by Pius XII
in a third syllabus, when it had become widespread within the Church
towards the middle of the century. The third syllabus is the encyclical
Humani Generis of 12 August 1950 and, with the texts of the Second Vatican Council, it
constitutes the Church's principal doctrinal pronouncement since
Pius X.
In the formation
of the Church's collective identity, there are moments of memory,
when certain parts of the deposit of faith are brought to attention,
and moments of oblivion, when certain parts of the Catholic
system are not adverted to and ate left in obscutity.47
This is an effect of the limited attention of the mind, which cannot
concentrate on everything all the time, and the mind's capacity
to be directed to one thing ot another is the great fact on which
the art of education, and at a lowet level that of propaganda, is
based. Since it is a necessary part of human nature, it can neither
be regretted nor eliminated. A relative inadvertence of this sort
must not, however, be allowed to turn into the abolition of parts
of the Catholic system. This or that aspect of the whole is highlighted
or obscured by the course of history, but these aspects are not
created or destroyed in the consciousness of the Church by such
prominence or the lack of it.
When the main
current of opinion in the Church drifts towards obscuring certain
truths, the teaching Church must forcefully uphold them so as to
preserve the Catholic system whole and entire, even if the main
current is not much interested in the truths concerned. Thus the
undeniable fact that the three syllabuses are at present ignored
does not rob them of the outstanding importance they intrinsically
have. One cannot help noticing in this connection that it is precisely
the coherence and continuity of these papal pronouncements which
constitute tlieir chief fault in the eyes of the innovators, since
the Church's emphatic reiteration of its teaching is held to block
further development. In fact the Church dwells in a timeless truth
by which she judges time. The Church's motto is bis in idem,
or pluries in idem, or even semper in idem,48because
she stands in a continual and unbreakable relationship with the
first truth, so that when she judges the changing events which are
truth's escort through time, it is the truth, not the events, which
drives her on.
47.
We
will discuss this forgetfulness in paragraph 330ff.
48.
“Twice, several times, always the same.”
28. Humani
Generis (1950).
The categorical
character of the encyclical's title immediately attracts attention
by not employing the more reserved expressions of other doctrinal
pronouncements. Instead of the usual formula non videntur consonare49
or something similar (which is in fact used here regarding polygenism),
it is declared at the outset that the opinions to be dealt with
are of a kind quae catholicae doctrinae fundamenta subruere minantur.50
It is only a threatened or prospective ruin, but the threat
is real: not subruere videntur,51but
subruere minantur. The errors are such as to threaten
Catholic doctrine, even if they have not overthrown it completely.
In the introduction
to this catalogue, one characteristic of the crisis is mentioned
which signals its importance and marks its novelty. The error which
once came ab extra, from outside the Church, now comes ab
intra; it is no longer a case of an external assault, but of
an intestine evil; no longer an attempt to demolish the Church,
but, in the famous phrase of Paul VI, a self-demolition of the
Church. But there should be no room for false opinions in the
Church, because in it human reason, without prejudice to its natural
capacities, is always strengthened and widened in its scope by Revelation.
The fundamental error however is precisely the postulate of independence
from Revelation, and the errors which the encyclical is to describe
are merely forms or denominations of it. So the Pyrrhonism essential
to the modern mentality will mean our knowledge is not a grasping
of the real, but merely the product of ever changing impressions
of an ever elusive reality. Knowledge is independent of truth.
Existentialism
is also based on this principle of independence. For it, existing
things have no relation to the divine ideas, those prior essences
which participate in the absoluteness of the divine being. The encyclical
reproves the modern mentality, not inasmuch as it is modern, but
inasmuch as it claims to detach itself from that firmament of unchangeable
values, and to give itself over wholly and solely to present existence.
Even with corrections, this mentality cannot be reconciled with
Catholic dogma.
The following
articles trace the descent of further errors, relating them all
back to the error of creaturely independence. Historicism, being
the consideration of existence detached from any fixed essence,
finds reality only in movement, and gives rise to a universal mobilism.
Indeed, once one does deny the transtemporal element in every
temporal thing, which consists precisely in its fixed nature, being
dissolves into becoming, to the exclusion of any abiding reality,
even though in fact the latter is necessary in order to conceive
of the very notion of becoming.53
The condemnation
of sentimentalism too,54
is simply a condemnation of feeling when not viewed in the context
of man as a whole. At the core of man is an essential relation to
his own reason, and at the core of reason is an essence which, though
created, participates in the absolute. The theoretical core of Pius
XII's document is that Pyrrhonism, existentialism, mobilism and
sentimentalism all draw their origin from a principle of independence,
opposed to the principle on which Catholicism rests. The censure
of particular errors deriving from this fundamental error is purely
secondary and accessory, be they the denial of the possibility of
metaphysics (whether Thomistic or not), the assertion of a universal
evolutionism, scriptural criticism, religious naturalism, and other
specific religious errors (among the most important being the denial
of transubstantiation); and one should set these apart at a secondary
level when one is trying to establish just where the very principle
of Catholicism itself is being attacked. That principle is that
everything anthropological depends on the divine, and that to deny
this dependence is, as the document declares, to dissolve the foundations
of every possible axiology.55
49.
“Do
not appear to harmonize.”
50.
“Which threaten to undermine the foundations of Catholic doctrine.”
51. “Seem to undermine.”
52.Denzinger, 2323.
53.Denzinger, loc. cit.
54. Denzinger, 2324.
55. Denzinger, 2323.
sections
added every week
Courtesy of the Angelus
Press, Kansas City, MO 64109
Only select chapters are presented here.
To buy the whole book please click
here
|