Chapter
15
Theological setting of the argument
147. Theological setting of the argument.
An analysis of the dizziness or the giddiness
and dislocation, that has entered the Church in the twentieth century,
could be conducted in purely philosophical terms. In Catholic epistemology
however, philosophy is a subordinate discipline that makes reference
to a faith that stands above it, and hence a philosophical consideration
of things is included as part of a higher view, which philosophy
serves without losing its own autonomy.
As we have indicated in the opening paragraphs
of this book, and as is generally recognized, the crisis in the
Church is a crisis of faith, but the link between mans natural constitution
and the supernatural life that is made connatural to him, rather
than simply superimposed upon him, means that a Catholic enquirer
must look for the origins of the crisis in an order deeper than
the purely philosophical.
Underlying the present confusion there
is an attack on mans powers of cognition, an attack that has implications
for the metaphysical constitution of being in general and of primal
Being as well, that is of the Holy Trinity. We will call the attack
by its historically expressive name of Pyrrhonism;1
it is something that attacks the very principle of all certainty,
not merely this or that truth of faith or reason, since what it
impugns is mans capacity to know any truth at all. There are two
points to be made about this wobbling of the axis around which all
certainties revolve. First; it is no longer an isolated and esoteric
phenomenon, a peculiarity of a particular philosophical school,
but something that permeates the mentality of the age and with which
Catholic thought has compromised. Second; it affects theology as
well as metaphysics because it penetrates to the constitution of
created being and therefore to that of uncreated being as well,
the former being an analogical imitation of the latter. As love
proceeds from the Word within the Trinity, so life proceeds from
thought in the human soul. If one denies the priority of thought
over life, of truth over the will, one is attempting a dislocation
of the Trinity. If one denies the capacity to grasp being, the expansion
of the spirit into its primal loving is left unconnected with truth,
loses any regulating norm and degenerates into a mere existence.
By turning away from the divine Idea, on the grounds that it is
held to be unreachable, human life is reduced to a pure mobilism
or becoming, devoid of any ideal values. Were it not for the impossibility
on God’s side that He should leave his creation to lapse into pure
movement, devoid of axiological form, man’s world would be a becoming
without substance, direction or goal.
A Pyrrhonism that posits a pseudo-absolute
alogism (pseudo because thought cannot deny itself) distorts the
ontological composition of the Trinity, and reverses its processions,
as we have said. If truth is unreachable, the dynamic of life no
longer proceeds from the intelligible but precedes it and indeed
produces it. The denial of the Idea, as Leopardi2
acutely saw, is strictly, ultimately and irrefutably a denial of
God, because it takes away from human life any trace of eternal
and indestructible values. If the will does not proceed from knowledge,
but produces and justifies itself, the world is deprived of any
rational basis and becomes a kind of meaninglessness. If one denies
the capacity of our intellect to form concepts corresponding to
the real, the more the mind is unable to apprehend and conceive
(that is take with itself) the real, the more it will develop its
own operation within itself by producing (that is bringing forth)
mere excogitations. These latter will be occasioned by something
that touches our faculties but is not present in the concept which
we form of it. Hence come all the ancient and modern sophisms that
trust in thought while at the same time lacking any confidence that
we can grasp the truth.
If thought does not have an essential
relation with being, it is not subject to the laws governing being
and ceases to be measured because it becomes itself the measurer.
Protagoras of Abderas saying well expresses the independence of
thought from being: man is the measure of all things.3
Gorgias of Leontini’s three propositions bear witness to a refusal
to grasp the object and to the arrogance of the mind that closes
itself upon itself: “Nothing exists. If something existed
it would be unknowable. If it were knowable, it would be inexpressible.”4
The arrogance of controversy has manifested
itself in every branch of knowledge, particularly at times when
a subjective spirit was in the ascendant. Setting aside the extravagances
of the Greek sophists and of those who deny the very existence of
Christ, I come to the Pyrrhonism of the contemporary Church.
1.
See note at paragraph 16. [Translator’s note.]
2.
Giacomo Leopardi (1798-1837). Italian romantic poet
and egotist. [Translator’s note.]
3.
Diels,74Bl.
4.
Ibid., 76 B 3. These three propositions are illogical if they are
taken without explanation, but become true if they are understood
as applying absolutely. It is in fact true that no finite being
perfectly is, that is to the full extent that it is possible to
be. No thing is perfectly knowable or perfectly expressible by us
in an exhaustive sense.
148. Pyrrhonism in the Church.
Cardinals Léger, Heenan, Alfrink and
Suenens.
The root of the confusion in the world
and the Church is Pyrrhonism, that is the denial of reason. The
charge commonly made, to the effect that modern civilization overestimates
the power of reason, is superficial. It would be true if one meant
by reason the mind’s capacity to calculate and construct, to which
we owe technology and our control over the things around us. But
that is one of the minds lesser faculties and is said to be found
in spiders and apes. If on the other hand one means the capacity
to grasp the being of things and their meaning, and to adhere to
them with the will, then the present world is much more inclined
to alogism than rationalism. In the third syllabus, Pius XII defended
verum sincerumque cognitionis humanae valorem ac certam et immutabilem
veritatis assecutionem5.
against the spirit of the age. Paul VI nobly declared: “We
are the only ones who defend the power of reason.6.
“In the doctrinal constitution Lumen Gentium, Vatican
II repeated the anti-pyrrhonist text of Vatican I: Deum omnium
rerum principium et finem naturali humanae rationis lumine certo
cognosci posse.”7.
Gaudium et Spes also condemns those who “no
longer admit any absolute truth.”8.
These assertions, however, do not reflect
the mentality of a large part of the council and are in contradiction
with post-conciliar developments. In the 74th sitting Cardinal Léger
maintained: “Many people think that the Church demands a too
monolithic unity. In recent centuries an exaggerated unity has been
introduced into the study of doctrines.”9.
It would seem that the Canadian cardinal can detect a lesser
degree of doctrinal unity in the non-recent centuries, when a death
penalty existed in some times and places for people who broke that
unity, and that he is moreover ignorant of the variety of theological
schools that are a feature of the Churchs life throughout history.
To this historical judgment, Léger attaches a value judgment of
a frankly pyrrhonistic kind: “Certainly the assertion that
the Church has the truth can be justified, if the necessary distinctions
are made. The knowledge of God, whose mystery is explored in doctrine,
prevents intellectual immobility”10
It seems the Cardinal is denying that, whether inside or outside
the Church, there are changeless truths, and that in his case Pyrrhonism
is based upon the divine transcendence, as if the fact that the
infinite cannot be infinitely known by the finite removed all knowledge,
when in fact it is knowledges foundation. Next the Cardinal misunderstands
the passage in St. Augustine that says we must seek in order to
find, and find in order to seek again, which is actually opposed
to Pyrrhonism: what is found is one thing, what is sought the next
time is another, not the same thing over again as if it had not
been found and could not become, in certain conditions, fixed for
ever.11.
Cardinal Heenan noted the relativist scepticism
that generally characterizes the Churchs teachers: “The magisterium
has survived only in the Pope. It is no longer exercised by the
bishops and it is rather difficult to get the hierarchy to condemn
a false doctrine. Outside Rome the magisterium today is so unsure
of itself that it no longer even attempts to lead.”12
This statement certainly condemns the renunciation of authority
but it also shows the pyrrhonistic uncertainty that has entered
the Church’s teaching body. During the fourth session of the council,
in a press conference on 23 September 1965 reported by the news
agencies, Cardinal Alfrink also notes the phenomenon, but unlike
the Englishman, he gives it a positive interpretation, expressing
his Pyrrhonism in set terms: “The council has got people thinking
and there is hardly a subject in the Church that has not been brought
into question.” Lastly Cardinal Suenens said to the French Catholic
intellectuals’ week at Paris in 1966; La morale est d’abord vive,
dynamisme de vie et soumise, à ce titre, à une croissance intérieure,
qui écarte toute fixité.13
It is obvious that the Cardinal is mixing up morality, an absolute
and unchangeable demand that imposes itself on man, and one’s moral
life that changes in each individual continually from one judgment
to the next. Morality is not a subjective dynamism but an absolute
rule which is a participation in the divine Reason.
5.
Denzinger 2320. “The true genuine
worth of human knowledge and the certain and immutable attainment
of truth.”
6.
O.R., 2 June 1972.
7.
Lumen Gentium, 6. “God, the beginning
and end of all things can be certainly known by the natural light
of human reason. “
8.
Gaudium et Spes, \9.
9.
O.R., 25-26 November 1963.
10.
O.R., 25 November 1963.
11.
What John Paul II said in his speech to the European
Council for Nuclear Research during a visit to Geneva is very apt
here: “One must unite the search for truth with the certainty
of already knowing the source of truth. “ O.R., 16 June 1982.
12.
O.R., 28 April 1968.
13.
“Morality is first and foremost alive, a dynamism
of life, and therefore subject to an interior growth that rejects
any kind of fixity. “ Documentation Catholique, No. 1468,
coll.605-6. This firmness of the mind in truth is seen as an evil;
the French bishops in their Missel pour les dimanches of
1983 got people to pray pour les croyants qui sont tentes de
s ‘installer dans leurs certitudes. “For believers who
are tempted to become fixed in their certitudes.”
149. The discounting of reason. Sullivan.
Innovators’ rejection of certainty.
Reason is openly discounted in Jean Sullivan’s
book Matinales.14
The author denies the distinction between faith and love, on the
grounds that it has no scriptural basis and he hence denies there
is a crisis of faith in the Church while not even stopping to realize
he is implicitly distorting the Trinity. Indeed one cannot talk
about a crisis, that is a discernment, when one has no fixed measure,
no means of discerning the difference between faith and non-faith,
or when one mixes up opposing ideas in a confused mass and regards
them as one. The difference between believing and loving is not,
in any case, based merely on Scripture; it rests on mans nature,
in which intellect and will are really distinct. Their distinction
is derived from the analogous distinction within the Trinity.
It is clear from what Sullivan says about
the incompatibility of faith and certainty that the ignoring of
this distinction means the radical overthrow of rationality: Les
croyants s’imaginent que lafoi va avec la certitude. On leur a mis
ça dans la têtel Ilfaut se méfier de la certitude. Les certitudes
sont généralement fondées sur quoi? Le non approfondissement des
connaissances.15
The book contains a great many absurdities
both logical and religious. If the author is saying that something
cannot be seen and believed simultaneously by the same person, he
is merely stating the obvious and repeating a philosophical truism.
But if he is saying one cannot have certainty about something that
is believed, he is departing from Catholic doctrine. It is a Catholic
dogma that faith involves certainty, and so is the proposition that
such certainty is not the privilege of mystical or simple souls,
but a light common to all the faithful. Secondly, Sullivan overthrows
any sound gnoseology when he reverses the relation between certainty
and the deepening of one’s knowledge. Certainty is the subjective
state of the knower precisely inasmuch as he really is a knower;
ignorance is a lack of knowledge and doubt is less than full knowledge.
Sullivan’s views remind one of the impious calumnies of Giordano
Bruno, set forth in his “Dialogues” on holy stupidity. They
are accompanied by another more fundamental error to the effect
that certainty and faith block the possibility of acting, so that,
in the author’s ill-found phrase, vivre c’est perdre lafoi.16
He maintains that any kind of stability in thought makes it impossible
to enter into communion with other minds, and that our own minds
should be kept permanently open to any and every point of view.
Catholic teaching holds instead that communion
involves something that remains the same amidst the movement of
life. It also says that life proceeds from thought, not thought
from life, just as theologically the Holy Spirit proceeds from the
Word, and not vice versa. Human activity is in fact driven by the
belief that one possesses truth, and the history of philosophy proves
the fact. The Ephectics of antiquity and all other systems that
advocate flight from action, seek to reduce our certainties so as
to deprive us of motives for action, their optimal goal being a
complete lack of certain knowledge that will bring us to the safe
haven of complete spiritual ataraxy or detachment.
Certainty is a mental state that follows
from a deepening of knowledge, not from shallowness as Sullivan
alleges. He denies the existence of any depth that cannot be surpassed,
any fundamental principle, any absolute. Pyrrhonism goes hand in
hand with its twin, mobilism, and like it, leads to blasphemy: Vivre
c’est aussi perdre la foi et s’apercevoir qu’on est possede par...C’est
pourquoi rencontrer Dieu c’est le renier à l’instant même.17
This is just trivial love of paradox, but behind the literary
device of paradox there is a denial of the Word and, as Leopardi
accurately saw, a denial of God.
14.
It was reviewed at length in I.C.I., No.506, September
1976, p.40, the most widely read publication of the newfangled sort
in France.
15.
“Believers imagine that faith goes with certainty.
People have put that idea into their heads! One should distrust
certainty. Certainties are generally founded on what? A shallowness
of knowledge.”
16.
“To live is to lose faith.”
17.
“To live is also to lose the faith and to realize that
one is possessed by...That is why to meet God is to deny him at
the same instant.”
150. The discounting of reason, continued.
The Padua theologians. The Ariccia theologians. Manchesson.
Let it not be thought that we have picked
out and exaggerated one or two cases in order to prove that Pyrrhonism
has penetrated the Church. We have pointed them out as symptoms,
not as oddities. The widespread mentality they indicate can be gauged
from the actions of whole bodies of thinkers, not just from notable
individuals.
The Congress of Italian Moral Theologians
in Padua in 1970 adopted this proposition: “Since the exercise
of reason is systematically included in a particular historical
set of circumstances, it cannot be exercised in universal terms.
“ This really does mean the destruction of reason and thus of everything
else, including congresses of moral theologians.
The Pyrrhonism of the Ariccia Congress
of Theologians, presided over by Cardinal Garrone, the Prefect of
the Congregation for Catholic Education is analogous. The Osservatore
Romano reported it without criticism.18
The dominant view was “no proposition can be held to be absolutely
true. “ There are, it was alleged, no rational prolegomena to theology “because
the word of God justifies itself and interprets itself.” The contradiction
of the Church’s theology here is less fundamental than the contradiction
of its philosophy Firstly, since man is a rational creature, his
faith cannot be something devoid of reasonableness. Secondly, the
word of God would only justify itself, as it is here alleged to
do, if it carried with it convincing evidence, since only evidence,
immediate or mediate, can justify an assertion. But in fact such
evidence is lacking where the message of faith is concerned and
it is accepted precisely through faith, and not on the basis of
convincing evidence. Thirdly, to say that the word of God interprets
itself is a mere concatenation of words, not a meaningful statement.
To interpret means literally to place oneself in the middle between
a word and its hearer, between the intelligible and the person exercising
intellection. The interpreter is a third who mediates between two
other things, and so the word of God cannot be said to stand between
itself and something else.
The Ariccia theologians go on from the
relation between philosophy and theology, straying into the field
of the relation between subject and object and state frankly that “to
speak in the categories of the man of our time, the theologian must
take account of the anthropological shift, which consists in an
inversion of the relationship between subject and object and in
the impossibility of apprehending the object in itself.” That is
an explicit formulation of Pyrrhonism and the destruction of Catholic
doctrine. Faith presupposes reason. It involves submission by the
reason but a submission willed by reason itself. The theological
congress’s theories are regressive and take philosophy back to pre-Socratic
positions. That they were accepted by a congress of Catholic theologians
presided over by a cardinal means either that an abuse of language
has occurred or that Catholic theology no longer exists.
Pyrrhonism drops its last veil in the
conclusion that: “For there to be a valid and effective meeting
with contemporary man, one must know the transcendental condition,
that is the general structure, of the man of today. “ If words mean
anything, this is to say that “transcendental” means the same
thing as “empirical.”
This Pyrrhonist vein has not been exhausted
in the more recent post-conciliar period, and continues to crop
up in official and semi-official statements. The colloquium held
at Trieste in January 1982 at the Centre for Theology and Culture,
the proceedings of which were published with an introduction by
the local bishop, ended by adopting this thesis: “An absolute
reason of an idealist or Marxist sort [or any other sort] that unfolds
itself in the concrete events of human history does not exist; there
is rather an historically given reason, the forms of which change
with the changing of cultural contexts. There can be no question
of readopting a totalizing metaphysical, philosophical and theological
view.”19
This is to invalidate reason, repudiate Providence, deny metaphysics
and set aside God.
Yves Manchesson of the Institut Catholique
in Paris puts the Churchs role in the world in these terms, in a
description of the state of the Church in France after the liberation:
L’Eglise essaie de déchijfrer les signes des temps, pense ne
pas avoir reponse à tout, cherche moins a préciser une vérité en
soi qu’une vérité pour tous les hommes.20
These expressions of the respected author seem
to us a mere compounding of words. First of all, the Church has
never claimed to be the depository of all truths, since there is
a whole world of knowledge that God has left to man’s investigation
and debate: et mundum tradidit disputationi eorum, ut non inveniat
homo opus quod operatus est Deus ab initio usque ad finem.21
This sphere comprises what might be called extra-moral matters
that do not involve human axiology and teleology, that is matters
that do not concern mans ultimate destiny. But the Church is, on
the other hand, the depository of all truth without which man cannot
fulfill his destiny and the destiny of the world.
Secondly, there is a prodigious carelessness
about the meaning of words in talking about a truth that is not
true in itself, but is nonetheless a truth for all men, since the
latter is surely an instance of the former, that is, a truth that
stands and lasts independent of its being apprehended by finite
minds. It is not the consent of man that gives truth its value,
as some dare to assert today; it is the truth that bestows value
on human opinions. A truth can exist in relation to man only if
it is in itself independent of man: per prius it exists in
itself and per posterius it is true for man.
18.
O.R., 16 January 1971.
19.
O.R.,8July 1983.
20. “The
Church tries to read the signs of the times, does not think it has
the answer to everything, is less concerned to define truth as such
than a truth for all men. “ Amities Catholiques Frangaises, April
1979.
21.
Ecclesiastes, 3:11. “And he gave the world over
to their disputing, and man could not fathom the work that God had
done from beginning to end.”
151. Dialogue and
discussionism in the post-conciliar Church. Dialogue in Ecclesiam
Suam.
The word dialogue represents the biggest change in the mentality
of the Church after the council, only comparable in its importance
with the change wrought by the word liberty in the last century.
The word was completely unknown and unused in the Church’s
teaching before the council. It does not occur once in any previous
council, or in papal encyclicals, or in sermons or in pastoral practice.
In the Vatican II documents it occurs 28 times, twelve of them in
the decree on ecumenism Unitatis Redintegratio. Nonetheless, through
its lightning spread and an enormous broadening in meaning, this
word, which is very new in the Catholic Church, became the master-word
determining post-conciliar thinking, and a catch-all category in
the newfangled mentality.1 People not only talk about ecumenical
dialogue, dialogue between the Church and the world, ecclesial dialogue,
but by an enormous catachresis, a dialogical structure is attributed
to theology, pedagogy, catechesis, the Trinity, the history of salvation,
schools, families, the priesthood, the sacraments, redemption, and
to everything else that had existed in the Church for centuries
without the concept being in anybody’s mind or the word occurring
in the language.
The movement from a thetic manner of talking, which was appropriate
to religion, to a hypothetic and problematic style, is apparent
even in the titles of books, which used to teach, but now enquire.
Books that were called Institutiones or “manuals” or
“treatises” on philosophy, theology or any other science
have been replaced by “Problems in philosophy,” “Problems
in theology,” and manuals are abhorred and despised precisely
because of their positive and apodictic nature. It has happened
in all areas: no more nurses’ manuals, but problems in nursing;
not drivers’ manuals but drivers’ problems and so on,
with everything moving from the certain to the uncertain, the positive
to the problematic. It is a decline from an intentional appropriation
of real objects by means of knowledge (signified by the syllable
no in nosco, I know) to a simple throwing of the object before the
mind (prohallo in Greek, from which we get problem).
In August 1964, devoting a third of his first encyclical Ecclesiam
Suam to dialogue, Paul VI equated the Church’s duty to evangelize
the world with a duty to dialogue with the world. But one cannot
help noticing that the equation is supported neither by Scripture
nor the dictionary. The word dialogue never occurs in Scripture
and its Latin equivalent colloquium is only used in the sense of
a meeting between chief persons and of a conversation, never in
the modern sense of a group meeting. Colloquium on three occasions
in the New Testament means a dispute. Evangelization is a proclamation
not a dispute or a conversation. The evangelization the Apostles
are commanded to undertake in the Gospel is immediately identified
with teaching. The very word angelos carries the idea of something
that is given to be announced, not something thrown into dispute.
It is true that Peter and Paul dispute in the synagogues, but it
is not a question of dialoguing in the modern sense of a dialogue
in search of something, setting out from a position of ostensible
ignorance, but rather a dialogue in refutation of errors. The possibility
of dialogue disappears, in their case, the moment the disputant
is no longer open to persuasion, whether through his obstinacy or
his incapacity. This can be seen, for example, in St. Paul’s
refusal of dialogue on one occasion.2 Just as Christ spoke with
authority: Erat docens eos sicut potestatem hahens,3 the Apostles
preached the Gospel in an authoritative manner, not looking to validate
it by dialogue. In the same place Christ’s positive way of
teaching is contrasted with the dialogues of the scribes and pharisees.
The heart of the matter is that the Church’s message is not
a human product, always open to argument, but a revealed message
designed to be accepted rather than argued about.
After having equated evangelization with dialogue, Ecclesiam Suam
denies that evangelization, or preaching the truth, means condemning
error, and it identifies condemnations with coercion. The theme
of the council’s opening speech thus returns.4
“Our mission,” the encyclical says, “is to announce
truths that are undeniable and necessary to salvation; it will not
come armed with external coercion, but with the legitimate means
of human education.” This is a legitimate and traditional
manner of approach, as was proved by the fact that immediately after
the encyclical’s publication, Wisser’t Hooft, the Secretary
of the World Council of Churches, hastened to state that the Pope’s
ideal of dialogue as a communication of truth without a reciprocal
reply, was not in accordance with ecumenical ideas.5
1In the Osservatore Romano of 15 March 1971, Cardinal Roy said
dialogue was a new experience for the Church and for the world.
On 15-16 November 1966, on the other hand, the Osservatore said
that the Church had always practiced dialogue (mixing it up with
controversy and refutation of other arguments) and that if there
had been times when it did not practice it, “they were more
or less depressed periods.”
2 Acts, 19:8-9.
3 Matthew 7:29. “He taught them as one having authority.”
4 See paragraph 38.
5 O.R., 13 September 1964.
152. Philosophy of dialogue.
The new fangled dialogue is based on “the perpetual problematicity
of the Christian subject,” as the Osservatore Romano puts
it,6 that is, on the impossibility of ever getting to anything that
is not itself problematic. In short it denies the old principle,
recognized in logic, metaphysics and morality, that anagke stenai.7
Dialogue first runs into trouble when it is made to coincide with
the Church’s universal task of evangelization and heralded
as a means of spreading truth. It is impossible for everyone to
dialogue. The possibility of holding a dialogue depends on the knowledge
one has of a subject, and not, as is alleged, on the fact of one’s
liberty or the dignity of one’s soul. The right to argue depends
on knowledge, not on man’s general ordering towards the truth.
Socrates said that on matters of gymnastics, one should consult
an expert in gymnastics, on horses an expert on things equine, on
wounds and diseases an expert in medicine and on the running of
society an expert in politics. Expertise is a result of effort and
study, of reflecting on things methodically and steadily rather
than nastily and extempore. Contemporary dialogue presupposes, however,
that any man is capable of dialoguing with anyone else on any subject,
simply in virtue of being a rational creature. The demand is therefore
made that the life of the temporal community and the Church should
be arranged so that everyone can participate; not as the Catholic
system envisages, by each person contributing his knowledge and
playing his own proper part, but by everybody giving his opinion
and deciding on everything. The paradox is that this right to argue
is being extended to everyone at the very moment when the knowledge
that gives an authentic title to join the argument is getting scarcer
and feebler even among the Church’s teachers.
The next blunder relates to the onus of proof. It is assumed that
dialogue can and should satisfy all the objections of an opponent.
Now for one man to offer himself to another with the aim of giving
him complete intellectual satisfaction on any point of religion
is a sign of a moral failing. It is rash for somebody who has asserted
a truth to proceed to expose himself to a general, extempore and
unlimited discussion. Every subject has many facets; he is familiar
with only some, or even one of them. Yet he exposes himself as if
he were ready for every objection, impossible to catch off guard,
and as if he had anticipated every possible thought that could arise
on the matter.
Dialogue labors under yet another difficulty from the side of the
inquirer, because it rests on a gratuitous presupposition that St.
Augustine perceptively detected in his day. An intellect can be
capable of formulating an objection without being capable of understanding
the argument that meets the objection. This fact, that an individual’s
intellectual strength may be greater in raising objections than
in understanding replies, is a common cause of error. Ecce unde
plerumque convalescit error, cum homines idonei sunt his rebus interrogandis
quihus intelligendis non sunt idonei.8
This disproportion between an intellect’s asking a question
and understanding a reply is a result of the general difference
between potency and act. Refusal to recognize this difference leads
to an illogical conclusion in politics: everyone has by nature a
capacity to be able to rule, therefore everyone can rule. It also
leads to the illogicality implicit in dialogue: everyone has by
nature a capacity to know the truth, therefore everyone actually
knows the truth.
In the first book of his Theodicy, Antonio Rosmini also teaches
that an individual should not trust his own intellectual powers
to solve the questions that arise regarding the workings of divine
Providence: no individual can be certain that his own intellectual
strength is up to meeting all the objections that might face it.
This uncertainty as to a person’s intellectual capacities
is what Descartes ignored in his method, when he imagined that the
power of reason was equally strong and equally exercisable in each
individual.
6 O.K., 15 January 1971.
7 “It is necessary to stop somewhere.”
8 De peccatorum mentis et remissione, lib. Ill, cap. 8. “Here
is a thing that often fosters error; when men are capable of enquiring
into things they are not capable of understanding.”
Courtesy of the Angelus
Press, Kansas City, MO 64109
Only select chapters are presented here.
To buy the whole book please click
here
|