This
issue of the Angelus English-Language edition of
SISINONO is the second part of a series
of two studies - one theological and one canonical - regarding
the "state of necessity" invoked by Archbishop
Lefebvre to justify his consecration of four bishops on
June 30, 1988. These remarks are for those who admit the
existence of an extraordinary crisis in the Catholic Church
but do not know how to justify the extraordinary action
of Archbishop Lefebvre on June 30, 1988 when, lacking permission
from Pope John Paul II, he transmitted the power of episcopal
orders to members of the Fraternity founded by him.
THEOLOGICAL
STUDY – PART II.
SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM POSED BY THE POPE’S “NO”
A. The Pope's "No"
We
saw in the first installment of this article (SISINONO,
"The 1988 Consecrations: Part I," The Angelus,
July 1999) that a bishop who experiences a state of grave
general necessity of souls and consecrates another bishop
"given that he has the power of Order" (St. Thomas
Aquinas, Supplement, Q.20, A.1, op.cit. in,
"The 1988 Consecrations: Part 1") is not questioning
the primacy of jurisdiction of the pope. We have seen that
he has every right to presume support for such an act required
by extraordinary circumstances "in order that adequate
provision be made" (ST, op. cit. in Part
1) for the salvation of souls and for the common good. The
salvation of souls is in fact the supreme law of the Church
and it is certain that the Church "supplies" the
jurisdiction lacking whenever it is a question of providing
for the "public and general necessity of the faithful"
(F.M. Cappello, SJ ., Summa Juris Canonici, vol.
I, p.258, n.258, §2, op. cit. in Part 1).
It
makes no difference to what we have just said if recourse
to the pope is made materially impossible by external circumstances,
as in the historical cases recalled by us [in Part 1].
But
it is the pope himself who is favoring or promoting a course
for the Church infected by neo-Modernism which threatens
the goods fundamental to souls, goods indispensable for
the salvation of souls, e.g., faith and morals. If
the pope himself is the cause or partial-cause, and even,
given his supreme authority, the ultimate cause of
the grave and general spiritual necessity in which there
is no hope of help from the lawful pastors, then what effect
will recourse to the pope obtain in such circumstances?
He will be physically accessible, but morally inaccessible.
Recourse to him will be certainly physically possible
but morally impossible, and if it be attempted,
it will result naturally in the pope's saying "No"
to the act which the extraordinary circumstances require
"in order that adequate provision be made" (ST,
op. cit. in Part 1) for the grave general necessity
of souls. Any different behavior on the part of the pope
presupposes, in fact, repentance and a humble admission
of his own responsibility given that the act in question
- i.e., the consecration of bishops -would not be
required if the pope himself was not in some measure co-responsible
for the state of grave and general necessity.
Therefore,
it remains for us to ask if the subject in such circumstances
is bound to obey the "No" of the pope despite
the harm threatening so many souls. In other words, does
the "No" of the pope exonerate him from the duty
under pain of mortal sin imposed by divine law upon whomever
has the possibility to provide help for souls in the state
of grave and general necessity where there is no hope of
help from lawful pastors? This is the question that finds
its answer in the Catholic doctrine on the state of necessity.
This will become clear as we explain the fourth, fifth,
sixth, and seventh principles of the Church's teaching on
this point. [The first, second, and third principles were
discussed in Part l-Ed.]
1.
4th Principle: In necessity the duty to help is independent
of the cause of the necessity and hence is binding be it
the superior himself who is placing souls in the state of
necessity
In
the state of necessity the duty to provide help arises independently
of the cause of that necessity, because "charity does
not look where the necessity comes from, but is only interested
in the fact that there is necessity."1
Thus, in the example we gave above in the sphere of natural
law, the wife has the duty to supply for her husband even
if it be the husband himself who is placing the family in
the state of necessity (SiSiNoNo, "The 1988
consecrations: Part 1," p.20).
Likewise,
the duty sub gravi [under pain of mortal sin- Ed.]
of helping souls in the state of grave necessity is binding
even if it is the bishop of the diocese who is spreading
or favoring Modernism, or, similarly, if it is the pope
promoting or favoring Modernism in the universal Church.
On the contrary, as we have already seen, it is precisely
this circumstance that gives rise to the grave duty of charity
because then the state of necessity of souls is without
any hope of help from those who ex officio should
be providing for people's ordinary and extraordinary needs.
These
circumstances, however, will have the effect of rendering
the duty of help more difficult and perhaps even heroic
on account of the easily foreseeable consequences. It will
be denied that there is any state of necessity! The rebuke
implied in the act of helping the people will draw down
upon whoever does so revulsion and unjust accusations. And,
since we are dealing with the person of the pope himself,
the subject runs into "even graver danger" because
"from the abuses of lesser prelates recourse can always
be had to the pope,"2
but against the pope the only recourse is to God (St. Catherine
of Siena).
2.
5th Principle: It is the character of the state of
necessity to suspend the superior's power of binding, and
if, nevertheless, he attempts to bind, what he commands
is not binding
Further
applying the example already given regarding natural law,
this principle is illustrated by the case of a husband who
not only placed his children in necessity or failed to provide
for them, but, who, moreover, prevented his wife from providing
for them as far as was in her power. It is obvious that
in such a case the husband's power to bind would be suspended,
and if he attempted to bind, his command would not be binding
upon his wife.
The
fact that in the case of Archbishop Lefebvre the superior
is the pope does not nullify this principle. The Vicar of
Christ first and foremost has the duty to provide for the
needs of souls, and if he does not provide for them (or,
worse, if he himself is the cause or part-cause of the grave
and general state of spiritual necessity), that does not
entitle him to prevent others from providing as far as they
can for the needs of souls. This is especially applicable
if the duty to supply is rooted in their own sacerdotal
or, still more, episcopal state.
The
authority of the pope is indeed unlimited, but from below,
not from above. >From above, papal power is limited
by divine law, natural and positive. The authority of the
pope is "monarchical...and absolute within the limits,
however, of divine law, natural and positive" and for
that reason "the Roman Pontiff himself cannot act against
divine law or disregard it."3
Now, in the state of necessity, divine natural and positive
law imposes a duty of charity under pain of mortal sin upon
whoever is able to provide help, and in the state of spiritual
necessity it imposes this duty above all on bishops and
upon priests {as well as on the pope). The pope, as like
any other superior, does not have the power to oppose this
duty {Suarez: " deest potestas in legislatore ad
obligandum" De Legibus, L. VI, cap. VII, n.ll).
That
is why it is said that "the state of necessity carries
its own dispensation with it because necessity is not subject
to law" {SI; I-II, Q.96, A.6). This is not to mean
that in the state of necessity it is lawful to do whatever
one wishes, but that "the action otherwise prohibited
is rendered lawful and permitted by the state of necessity
."4 This
is in order to safeguard higher interests than obedience
to the law or to the Superior. In such a case it is not
within the power of any superior to demand the observance
of the law in the usual way, because to no superior {and
still less to the pope) is it granted to exercise authority
harmful to anyone else, especially if that harm is spiritual
and involves many souls and violates one's duty of state,
especially that of a priest or bishop.
Not
even God, the Supreme Legislator, is bound in the state
of necessity ."That is why Christ Himself excuses David,
who in grave danger ate the breads of proposition which
the laity were forbidden to eat by Divine Law."5
According to this principle, not only do human laws cease
to oblige in a state of necessity, but even divine-positive
and affirmative divine-natural law cease (e.g., "Honor
thy father and mother"; "Remember to keep holy
the Sabbath Day"). The only law binding in the state
of necessity is negative divine-natural law {e.g.,
"Thou shalt not kill," etc.) . This is
because negative divine-natural law prohibits actions that
are intrinsically evil and hence forbidden because they
are evil, as opposed to actions which are evil only because
they are forbidden, such as the consecration of bishops
without pontifical mandate.
3
.6th Principle: It is the character of necessity to place
the subject in the physical or moral impossibility of obeying
It
is certain that God binds nobody in a state of necessity,
but the human legislator "can say 'no' without reason
and in violation of natural and eternal law"6
and therefore they can in fact forbid an action required
by the state of necessity. But, since the pope's "No"
is powerless to do away with the grave general necessity
of souls and hence the associated duty sub gravito
go to their help, the subject, especially if he is a bishop
or priest, then finds himself in the moral and absolute
impossibility of obeying, because he could not obey without
himself sinning and harming others. Hence, it is the character
of the state of necessity "to create a sort of impotency
whereby it is impossible to do something commanded or not
do some- thing forbidden."7
This
is not, in fact, the case of authority not being bound to
oblige because" summum ius summa iniuria,"
or one which issues an inopportune command lacking in prudence,
but which nevertheless people could be bound to obey all
the same in view of the common good. This is, on the other
hand, the case of authority that cannot oblige, because
its command is opposed to a precept of divine and natural
law "more grave and obliging."8
In such a case to obey the law or the legislator would be
"evil and a sin" (Suarez, De Legibus, L. VI, c.
VII, n.8). St. Thomas calls obedience in such a case "evil"
(SI; 11-11, Q120, A.1). Cajetan refers to it as a "vice"
(Cajetan in 1.2, q.96, a.6). Hence, refusal to obey becomes
a duty (i.e" inoboedientia debita).9
The
reality of such a case is not that the subject is disobeying.
It is better said that he is obeying a higher and
more compelling command issuing from divine authority, which
"commands us to regard higher interests."10
Human authority , in fact, "is neither the first nor
the only rule of morality ."6
Earthly authority is a" norma normata, "that
is to say, a rule itself regulated by divine law, and hence
when human authority, "contrary to natural and eternal
law,"6 says "No," then disobeying
man in order to obey God becomes a duty."11
4.
7th Principle: He who, constrained by the state of necessity,
does not obey, is not questioning the lawful exercise of
authority
For
there to be disobedience, the command or prohibition must
be lawful. This is the case when the Roman Pontiff or the
Ordinary have the power to make the command or prohibition
and, at the same time, the subjects are bound to obey the
command or prohibition.12
But, we have seen: 1) that even for the pope the
principle holds that, when the application of a law "would
be contrary to the common good or to natural law [and in
our case even divine-positive law-Ed.]...it is not
in the power of the legislator to oblige,"13
and, 2) that the state of necessity, especially the
necessity of which we are speaking, creates in the subject
"a condition of impotency or impossibility [in this
case morally and absolutely-Ed.] of doing a thing
commanded or not doing a thing forbidden."7
Therefore,
the command or prohibition of a superior which, by reason
of extraordinary circumstances, results in harm to souls
and the common good, as well as being contrary to the state
of the subject (cf. Suarez, De religione,
LX, cap.IX, n.4), loses its character of lawfulness and
absolves the subject from his duty to obey, "...nor
are those who behave in such a way, to be accused of having
failed in obedience, because if the will of leaders is repugnant
to the will and the laws of God, these leaders exceed the
measure of their power."14
We
have already quoted St. Alphonsus that in the state of necessity
there is imposed a "divine and natural law to which
the human law of the Church cannot be opposed," and
hence not even the command of the pope. The primacy of jurisdiction
of the pope, therefore, is not in any way called into question
by a violation of a jurisdictional law (as we have already
seen), nor is it called into question by disobedience motivated
by a state of necessity. In fact, the priest or bishop who,
constrained by necessity, does not obey the pope is not
thereby denying his own subordination to the pope outside
the case of necessity, and so he is not refusing authority
in its lawful exercise. Similarly, a wife is not denying
the authority of her husband outside of the case of necessity,
in which she has the duty to supply for him against his
unreasonably opposed will.
St.
Thomas says that whoever acts in a state of necessity "is
not setting himself up as a judge of law" or of the
legislator, nor is he even claiming that his point of view
is better than that of authority, but he is merely "judging
the particular case in which he sees that the words of the
law [and/or the command of the legislator - Ed.]
must not be observed," because their observance in
this particular case would be gravely harmful. Hence, the
state of necessity frees the subject from the accusation
of arrogating to himself a power that does not belong to
him (ST, I-II, Q.96, A.6, ad. 1,2). G. Gerson, for
his part, reminds us that "contempt of the keys must
be evaluated on the basis of legitimate power and the legitimate
use of power."14
Hence,
a priest who does not obey the pope forbidding him to absolve
in a state of necessity, or a bishop who does not obey the
pope forbidding him to consecrate bishops required by the
grave spiritual necessity of many souls threatened in their
faith and morals and without hope of help from their lawful
pastors, cannot be accused of "contempt of the keys."
This is so because the pope's action against divine law
(natural and positive) is not making "lawful use"
of his authority.
The
primacy of the pope means blind submission "without
examination of the object" exclusively "in matters
of faith and morals," and when the pope expresses himself
at that level on which his authority is infallible; otherwise,
submission to the pope would be subject to the moral norms
which regulate obedience. Hence, if the pope exceeds the
"measure" of his power, the subjects who obey
"God rather than man" are not to be accused of
having failed in obedience (cf. Leo XIII, Diuturnum
Illud, available from Angelus Press. Price: $0.75).
In
the case we are considering, Archbishop Lefebvre did not
question the right of the Vicar of Christ to exercise control,
by virtue of his primacy, over the power of the episcopal
order. He simply questioned whether the papal control over
episcopal consecrations was able, in the present extraordinary
circumstances, to be respected without grave harm to many
souls and without grave fault on his own part. These are
circumstances in which, as Pope John Paul II himself recognized,
"ideas opposed to the revealed and constantly taught
truth are being scattered by handfuls," when "true
and genuine heresies are being spread in the realm of dogma
and morals," and when Christians "in large part...lost,
confused, perplexed, while being tempted by atheism, by
agnosticism, by a vaguely moralistic humanism, by a sociological
Christianity without defined dogmas and without objective
morals,"11...are
generally without hope of help from their lawful pastors.
Likewise,
Archbishop Lefebvre did not question the Pope's power to
command bishops in the interests of the Church and of souls,
but he simply questioned whether in the present extraordinary
circumstances he could obey the Pope without grave harm
to the Church and to souls, and without himself committing
a grave sin, since he was under the grave duty of supplying,
a duty imposed by charity and rooted in his episcopal state.
And, in materially violating the disciplinary norm and the
command he had received, he took care to affirm the dogmatic
foundation of the primacy of the Holy Father and confine
himself strictly within the limits of Catholic doctrine
on the state of necessity. This was done in such a way that
Cardinal Gagnon himself announced that "Archbishop
Lefebvre has not in fact made the claim, 'I have the power
to act in this realm.'"15
To
maintain that by resisting the Pope's "No" Archbishop
Lefebvre was denying the primacy of the Pope, one would
have to claim that whoever resists a harmful command on
the part of authority is denying authority itself, which
is false.
These
things having been said, we may now judge the position of
those critics of Archbishop Lefebvre who would agree that
the pope ought never to forbid an action necessary to save
a man in peril of physical death, yet who simultaneously
claim the pope has power to forbid an action necessary to
help souls exposed to danger of eternal spiritual death.
They defend his power [to prohibit an action] in order to
safeguard the very primacy that is granted to the pope to
save souls, not to damn them.
Gerson
says that they are "weak-hearted" who think "that
the pope is a god who has all power in heaven and on earth,"2
but the critics of Archbishop Lefebvre make the pope - or
so it seems to us - more than a god, because not even God
issues any command harmful to souls, nor does He insist
on being obeyed when souls are being harmed. In reality,
these unjust critics are making the primacy of Peter into
the supreme law of the Church, which it is not, because
that primacy has for its purpose the saving of souls. These
critics are bringing papal primacy down to the level of
a tyranny and the obedience due to the pope to the level
of slavery, and they are making obedience the greatest of
all virtues, which it is not, at least according to Catholic
doctrine, for which obedience, even to the pope, is subordinate
to the exercise of the theological virtues, charity being
in the first place.16
St. Thomas, answering the objection that "sometimes
to obey we must omit doing what is good," replies that
"There is a good which a man is bound to do necessarily,
such as loving God or other similar things. And that good
may in no way be neglected out of obedience"
(ST,II-II, Q.I04, A.3, ad.3) [emphasis added]. Among
these "other similar things" there are in the
first place the duties of one's state of life (especially
if one is a Catholic bishop) and the love of neighbor, contained
as a secondary object within the love of God. In fact, everything
in the Church, with its hierarchical constitution, the primacy
of Peter and the laws that control the power of Order, have
charity as their final purpose, and if "necessity is
not subject to law" (ST, cit.), it is
because it is subject to the supreme law, which is charity.
To the law of charity are subject even the Vicars of Christ
who have, yes, the primacy of jurisdiction and hence the
right to control all other jurisdiction within the Church,
but:
...by
the divine, indeed even natural, precept of charity, they
are bound in this to provide sufficiently for the needs
of the faithful (Suarez, De poenitentiae sacramento,
disput. XXVI., Sect. IV, n.7).
|
In
Archbishop Lefebvre and the Vatican you will
find a complete set of the documents exchanged between
Rome and Archbishop Lefebvre in the time leading up
to and immediately following his episcopal consecrations
of June 30, 1988. Available from Angelus
Press. Price $12.95 plus shipping and handling. |
B.
A Word on Epikeia
That
which is called by the Church "necessary" epikeia,
or "epikeia without recourse to the superior"17
rests upon the four principles cited above in this second
part of our theological study (pp.18,19). Epikeia is
being taken here in its broad and correct sense in which
it is to be identified with equity, which is the
highest form of justice (ST, II-II, Q.120, A.l).
This true epikeia is a virtue concerning precisely
“duties arising in particular cases out of the ordinary”
(ST, II-II, Q.80), and which therefore comes to be
identified in Canon Law with the norms of “cessation ‘in
itself’ of the law in a particular case” and of “causes
excusing“ observance of the law and/or obedience to the
lawmaker.18 [Epikeia
(or equity) is a favorable and just interpretation not
of the law itself but of the mind of the legislator, who
is presumed to be unwilling to bind his subjects in extraordinary
cases where the observance of the law would cause injury
or impose too severe a burden. – Ed.]
In
his Dictionary of Canon Law, Naz writes that of St.
Thomas Aquinas:
…the
coming into play of epikeia is subordinate to the
existence of a right. In fact, in certain
cases, the law loses its power to bind – as where its
application would be contrary to the common good or to
natural law – and in such a case it is not in the power
of the legislator to bind or to oblige.19..There
is a place for epikeia because the will of the
legislator either is not able or is not bound to impose
the application of the law to the case in question.20
The
state of necessity in the case of Archbishop Lefebvre is
precisely the case in which the lawmaker cannot impose the
application of the law because it has become, by force of
particular circumstances, contrary to the common good and
to the divine natural and positive law. On his part, under
the pressure of a precept of divine natural and positive
law, “…the subject [e.g., Archbishop Lefebvre – Ed.]
not only may, but he is bound not to observe the law, whether
he asks or does not ask for permission to do so from the
superior.”21
Regarding
seeking permissions from the superior, Suarez explains (speaking
precisely of the pope) that here, “it is not a question
of interpreting the will of the superior,
but [a question] of his power” in order to
know what is not necessary to ask the superior, because
it is permitted to make use of “doctrinal rules” or “principles
of theology and law,”22
given that “one knows with more certitude the power
[of the superior] which is not free, rather than
his will, which is free [emphasis added].”23
For that reason the subject, having prudently examined the
circumstances and been informed by the “doctrinal rules”
or by the “principles of theology and law” that is “beyond
the power of legislator”24
to bind anyone to respect the law when it causes grave
harm to so many souls, and that to obey in such a case would
be “evil and a sin,”25
he may not - indeed, he must not
- submit to the law or to the command“on his own authority,”26
“by his own judgment.”27
Hence, by his own initiative, he refuses submission “without
recourse to the superior,”28
that is to say, without any dispensation or approval on
the part of the said superior. The reason, writes Suarez,
is:
that
in such a case the authority of the superior cannot have
any effect; indeed, even if he were to will that the subject,
after having had recourse to him, should observe the law,
the latter would not be able to obey him because he must
obey God rather than man and hence in such a case its
is out of place (“impertinens”) to ask for permission.29
Such
would be the case of the wife who, faced by the grave necessity
of her children, does not need the consent of her husband
to fulfil her duty to supply, and even were her husband
to forbid her to do so, she would not owe him obedience,
and hence it would be out of place to ask for his consent,
knowing him to be hostile.
Asking
if the danger of harm to oneself or to others excuses from
obeying, Suarez replies that
…one
does not presume in the lawmaker that he has the will
to bind in such case and even if he had, it would be without
effect. On this point all doctors are agreed who treat
of obedience and of laws.30
For
the reason, when it is established for certain that the
law in a particular circumstance has become unjust or
contrary to another command or virtue which is more binding,
then the law ceases to oblige and on his own initiative
he can disregard the law without having recourse to the
superior,31
given that the law in that case could not be observed
without sin nor could the superior bind his subject to
respect it without sin.32
There
remains, however, the duty to avoid scandal of neighbor,
and for that reason every opportune and humble means must
be attempted with regard to the Supreme Pontiff. But if
a humble insistence serves no purpose, then it is necessary
to exercise a manly and courageous liberty.2
C. REFUTATION
OF MORE FALSE OBJECTIONS
Hence,
it is not true that “it is only permitted to use epikeia
if the legislator is inaccessible,” as we read in the tract,
Du sacre episcopal contra la volonté du Pape (p.49),
published by the Fraternity of St. Peter. What it says is
true for epikeia in the strict or improper sense,
but not for epikeia in the broad and proper sense.
In the case of its improper (or popular) sense, epikeia
persumes that authority – out of its kindness – does
not wish to oblige, although it has the power to do so and
hence, if the lawmaker is accessible, there is the duty
to ask him, given that it is a question of “his will which
is free” (Suarez, cit.). On the other hand, epikeia
in the broad and proper sense concerns those cases in which
authority cannot oblige, even if it wishes to do so, and
the subject finds himself in the moral impossibility of
obeying. Hence, epikeia is “necessary” (Suarez),
and therefore recourse to the legislator is per se not
obligatory. Indeed, it must be left out whenever it is foreseen
that the superior would try to make his command binding
despite the harm to the person making the request or to
anyone else. In such a case, in fact, we are dealing not
with the will of the superior, but his “power, which is
not free” (Suarez, cit.).
Even
less true is what we read in De Rome et d’ailleurs
that a “state of necessity” arises when it is impossible
to contact the superior, which presupposes a certain urgency
in the decision to be taken.34
This is true for epikeia in the improper or popular
sense, but even then it is true only in part because the
state of necessity does not arise from the impossibility
of contacting the superior, but it exists independently
of that impossibility of contacting him, and it persists
independently of an eventual refusal from the superior.
To
settle the question, we quote Fr. Tito Centi, O.P.:
Moralists
have sought to fix the criteria to be laid down for the
application of epikeia. In substance, these criteria
come down to the three following cases: a)
when in a particular situation, the prescriptions of the
positive law are in opposition to a superior law which
binds one to regard higher interests [i.e., epikeia
in the proper sense]; b) when, for
reason of exceptional circumstances, submission to the
positive law would be too burdensome, without there resulting
a good proportionate to the sacrifice being demanded;
c) when, without becoming evil as
in the first case and without imposing an unjustified
heroism as in the second case, the observance of the positive
law runs into special and unforeseen difficulties which
render it, as it turns out, harder than it should have
been according to the intention of the legislator.35
The
grave spiritual necessity of many souls comes under the
first case "a)" above, the case
of positive law which by the force of extraordinary circumstances
becomes "evil" because "it is in opposition
to a superior law binding one to regard higher interests"
(i.e., epikeia in the proper sense - Ed.).
The authors of the tract, on the contrary, like the writer
of the article in the above-mentioned publication, seem
to admit only the second and the third cases, "b)"
and "c)" (i.e., epikeia in
the improper or popular sense), which have nothing to do
with the case of Archbishop Lefebvre. In the first case
"a)," which is the case of Archbishop
Lefebvre, epikeia coincides with equity, and, hence
involves the moral impossibility of obeying and is, as we
have already seen, a right [besides being a duty]. On the
other hand, in the second and third cases noted in "b)"
and "c)," epikeia is simply
identified with clemency or moderation in the application
of laws and in the exercise of authority.18
We
are in exceptional circumstances and, therefore, must ascend
to higher principles which are not preached every day and
which, therefore, are unknown to many, but which, nevertheless,
are able to be found succinctly summarized in any treatise
on the general principles of law or moral theology. Thus
for example, in the Institutiones Morales Alphonsianae
of Fr. Clement Marc we read:
A
place is given to epikeia whenever the law makes itself
harmful or too burdensome. In the first case [i.e.,
harmful], the superior really could not oblige and hence
epikeia is necessary [(§174) which is the case
as it concerns us here - Ed.].
In
Regarding Principles of Moral Theology (III, n.199),
Noldin says:
It
is said that the purpose of the law ceases "contraire"
[through contrary custom - Ed.] when its observation is
harmful. If the purpose of the law in a particular case
ceases "contraire," the law ceases [to
oblige]. The reason is that if the purpose of the law
ceases "contraire," then one has the right to
use epikeia.
Finally,
any manual explaining the principles of Canon Law deals
with the cessation "ab intrinseco" of the
law, that is to say, with the law that ceases to oblige
out of the simple fact that it is in such-and-such a case
harmful, and not because the lawmaker decrees that it should
cease, or grants a dispensation from it. Such is exactly
the case of the state of necessity, which is the strongest
reason excusing one from obedience and strict observance
of the law.36 This is especially true when this
state of necessity arises from the duty, rooted in one's
state, to help many souls in grave spiritual necessity,
because "the salvation of souls is, for spiritual society,
the ultimate end towards which all its laws and institutions
are oriented."16 This is true for the entire
hierarchy of the Church, top to bottom.
D. CONCLUSION
The
conclusion of our study is that either one denies the state
of necessity - the way chosen by the Vatican - or, if one
admits there is a crisis, then one must approve the action
of Archbishop Lefebvre. His decision, no matter how out
of the ordinary it may seem, must be judged in relation
to the out-of-the-ordinary situation in which it was carried
out. Therefore, "it is necessary to judge [it] on the
basis of higher principles than ordinary laws" (ST,
II-II, Q.54, A.4). From these principles which we have laid
out over the two parts of this theological study, it follows
that:
- Archbishop
Lefebvre had the duty under pain of mortal sin [sub
gravi], at least out of charity [ex caritate],
rooted in his episcopacy, to aid souls turning to him
for help in the present state of grave general necessity,
in which they could not and still cannot hope for help
from their lawful pastors;
- Archbishop
Lefebvre, while the actual extraordinary circumstances
required, had the duty, "given that he had the power
of Holy Orders to do so" (ST, cit.),
to consecrate other bishops in order to insure (through
other priestly ordinations) for the faithful in grave
general necessity that which they have a right to demand
from the hierarchy [i.e., sane doctrine and sacraments
- Ed.]. It is lawful and dutiful to help one's
neighbor in a state of necessity as far as one's powers
permit"37;
- It
was morally impossible for Archbishop Lefebvre to obey
the "No" interjected by the Pope because he
would have sinned by omission against the commandment
of charity, rooted in his episcopal state, a commandment
"greater and more binding" than obedience to
the law or to the lawmaker (Suarez, cit.). The
sin of omission, in fact, consists in not providing a
good which is on some account due whenever there would
be time to provide it (ST, II-II, Q.79, A.3ff).
In the case of Archbishop Lefebvre, this is the claim
of charity rooted in his episcopal state. Any law whatsoever
per se ceases to bind without dispensation nor
consent of the superior if the harm deriving from the
law is general and great [Suarez, De Legibus, L.
VI, c.IX, n.19];
- The
action of Archbishop Lefebvre out of grave and general
necessity of souls, compelled by a precept of divine natural
and positive law, neither denied the Pope's primacy of
jurisdiction nor disobeyed the Pope who himself "cannot
act against divine law nor disregard it."3
The
fact that the Vatican has denied there is any state of necessity
does not annul the grave necessity in which so many souls
are presently to be found. Rather, its denials confirm that
this state of necessity is, at least for the time being,
without any hope of relief from the Holy See. For that reason,
to the authors of Du sacre episcopal contre la volonté
du Pape who object that "St. Eusebius [of Samosata)
acted without the pope's consent but not against the pope's
consent, " we reply that only a question of fact
is at stake, not of principle. We concede that St.
Eusebius was not faced with the "No" of a pope
who promoted and favored Arianism, and demanded respect
for laws which would have deprived of help souls placed
in grave spiritual necessity. But, had St. Eusebius found
himself in that position, he would have had to follow the
moral principles recalled above and to fulfil, not "against"
the pope's "No" but despite the pope's "No,"
the most serious duty of charity laid upon his episcopacy
by the grave and general necessity of souls.
The
authors of the tract criticize what they call arguments
of an "illuminist" or "charismatic"
kind, meaning by this those who have made with simplicity
an act of confidence in the uprightness of Archbishop Lefebvre.
They are theologically wrong to do so. St. Thomas writes:
In
cases that happen rarely, and in which it is necessary
to depart from the ordinary law...a virtue of judgment
is needed based upon these higher principles, a virtue
which is called gnome and which implies a particular
perspicacity of judgment (ST, II-II, Q.51, A.4).
This
special "perspicacity of judgment," says St. Thomas,
can be possessed only by virtue of holiness:
The
spiritual man receives from the habit of charity the inclination
to judge rightly of everything according to divine laws,
arriving at his judgment by means of the gift of wisdom,
even as the just man arrives at his judgment in accordance
with the rules of law through the virtue of prudence (ST,
II- II, Q.60, AA.l,2).
In
this continuing study we are leaving to the side the sanctity
of Archbishop Lefebvre to confine ourselves to the general
principles of theology and Canon Law, so that the truth
is clear to all those admitting there is a crisis in the
Church. This truth is that in the present extraordinary
circumstances, one need not believe in obedience at all
costs (even if it cost the Faith or the salvation of souls).
Nor need one accept the non-provable "sedevacantist"
theses. There is a third way: to observe what the Church
teaches concerning the "state of necessity." That
is exactly what Archbishop Lefebvre did.
Hirpinus
(edited by Rev. Fr. Kenneth Novak)
(This
article ends the theological aspect of this continuing
study of the 1988 Episcopal Consecrations. Part 3 will
appear in the November
1999 SISINONO insert in The Angelus taking
up the canonical arguments supporting the validity
of Archbishop Lefebvre's action to consecrate four bishops.)
1. Suarez,
De caritate disp. IX, sectio II, n.3.
2.
G. Gerson, De contemptu clavium et materia excommunicationum
et inrregularitatum, considerations VII-XII, Opera,
Basilea 1489, prima pars, f33, quoted in La scomunica
di Girolamo Savonarola of Fr. Tito Centi, O.P., ed.
Ares, Milano.
3. P.
Palazzini Dictionarium moral et canonicum under "episcopus."
4.
Enciclopedia Cattolica under "stato di necessita."
5. H.
Noldin SJ., Summa Theologiae moralis, vol.I, De
Principiis L.III, q.8, 203.
6.Robert-Palazzini,
Dizionario di teologia morale under resistenza
al potere injuisto.
7. Dictionnaire,
Droit Canonique under "nécessité "
col.,991
8. Suarez,
De Legibus, L. VI, c. VII, n.12.
9. P.
Palazzini, Dictionarium morale et canonicum under
"oboedientia."
10.
Tito Centi, O.P., La Somma Teologica, ed. Salani
vol.XIX, nota I, p.274.
11.Roberti-Palazzini,
Dizionario cit. Resistenza al potere inguisto;
v. Leo XIII, Libertas
12.P.
Palazzini, Dictionarium, cit. under "inoboedientia."
13.
Naz, Dictionnaire Droit Canonique under “epikie.”
14.Leone
XIII, Diuturnum Illud.
15. Interview
in 30 Days, March, 1991.
16.
P. Palazzini, Dictionarium cit. under "oboedientia."
17.F.
Suarez, De Legibus, 1, VI, c.VIII, n.1
18.
V. Roberti-Palazzini, Dizionariao di Teologia morale,
ad. Studium, under "equita." See also:
"aequitas canonica" cit., and Naz, Dictionnaire
Droit canonique under "equite."
19.
Naz, Dict. cit. "epikie," col.366.
20.
Naz, loc. cit.
21.
Suarez, De Legibus, L.VI, c.VII, n.11.
22.
Suarez, op. cit. n.4.
23. Suarez,
op. cit. n.6.
24. Suarez,
De Legibus, L. VI, c. VII, n.11.
25.
Ibid. L. VI, c. VIII, n.8.
26. Ibid.
L. VI, c. VIII, n.1.
27.
ST, I-II, Q.80.
28.
Suarez, De statu perfectionis/De voto oboedientia,
L.X, c.IV, n.15.
29.
Ibid.
30. Suarez,
De statu perftctionis/De voto oboedientia, L.X,c.IV,n.15.
31.
Suarez, De Legibus, L.VI, c.VIlI, n.1.
32.
Suarez, op. cit. n.2.
33. Naz,
Dictionnaire Droit Canonique under "epikie,"
col. 369ƒƒ.
34. De
Rome et d'ailleurs, Sept.-Oct., 1991, p.17.
35.
La Somma Teologica, ed. Salani, vol. XIX, nota 1,
p.247.
36. Naz,
Dict. Droit Canonique under "excuse,"
col.633.
37.
P. Palazzini, Dictionarium cit. under "iurisdictio
suppleta."
Courtesy of the Angelus
Press, Kansas City, MO 64109
translated from the Italian
Fr. Du Chalard
Via Madonna degli Angeli, 14
Italia 00049 Velletri (Roma)
|